Appendix II: Time, Number, and Ideal Genesis in Aristotle and Plato


Becker: Mathematical Existence and the Temporality of the Infinite



Download 209.01 Kb.
Page2/5
Date28.05.2018
Size209.01 Kb.
#51247
1   2   3   4   5

Becker: Mathematical Existence and the Temporality of the Infinite

The investigations of Oskar Becker and Albert Lautman into the sense and structure of mathematical truth and existence are still little-known in contemporary scholarship.54 However, since both develop these questions under the dual condition of the most decisive formal results of the twentieth century and the extension of Heidegger’s own ontological problematic, these investigations bear, in both cases, importantly and even decisively on the further development of this problematic in our time.

Oskar Becker’s work Mathematische Existenz was published in 1927 in the same issue of the Jahrbuch fur Phenomenologische Forschung that contained the first edition of Heidegger’s Being and Time. Here, Becker undertakes to investigate the “being-sense” [Seinsinn] of mathematical phenomena through the research methodology of “hermeneutic phenomenology,” here understood as “ontology” in Heidegger’s sense of a “hermeneutics of facticity.”55 In particular, according to Becker, it is essential that the question of the meaning of mathematical existence be posed in relation to the structural basis of factically existing “human Dasein,” which, Becker follows Heidegger in suggesting, provides the foundation for the unity of all possible interpretation of meaning.56 Thus, the interpretation of mathematical existence must always refer back to the phenomenological interpretation of the mode of life in which the activity of “mathematicizing” (mathemaitikeusthai, analogously to philosophizing or making music) takes place and it is the structure of this life that must provide the ultimate guideline for understanding its deliverances or productions.57

Becker takes the basic directive for his interpretation of the sense of mathematical existence from the (then-contemporary) debate in the foundations of mathematics between the formalism of Hilbert and Bernays and the intuitionism of Brouwer and Weyl. Because of the decisive way in which the structure of the infinite enters into foundational research through Cantor’s set theory and other advances of nineteenth and early-twentieth century mathematics, the question of the nature and accessibility of the infinite is crucial to this debate and its possible resolution. For the formalist, access to infinite structures is possible only on the basis of a “proof theory” that sees mathematical proofs as, themselves, combinatorial mathematical structures that are necessarily finite.58 This gives rise to the problem of demonstrating the noncontradictoriness of particular axiom systems and of providing axioms which allow the noncontradictory specification of infinite sets and totalities. For the intuitionist, by contrast, no mathematical object or set is demonstrated to exist unless, and until, it is concretely provided to the actual intuition of the mathematician. Moreover, for the intuitionist, “only finite discrete wholes” can be so given.59 On this conception, the infinite, for instance the infinite series of whole numbers, can be given only through what Weyl calls a “basic arithmetic intuition” of the unlimited possible progression of the series 1, 2, 3, 4…. More generally, according to intuitionism it is possible to give an unlimited series of natural numbers only insofar as it can be specified through a finitely intuitible formula (for instance, the series 1, 4, 9, 16… through the formula: n2), and such a series is to be considered existent only insofar as it has actually been developed at any time.60

As Becker notes, the intuitionist conception suggests cases in which the law of excluded middle must be suspended, in particular in the case of the progressive development of infinite series or decimal extensions.61 For in these cases, with respect to the question whether there is or is not, in the future development of the series, a number with a specific property, the disjunction between a positive and a negative answer is not to be considered as exclusive until one or the other answer is actually obtained.62 This constraint is basically, as Becker points out, a consequence of the intuitionist insistence that all mathematical knowledge must be seen as an intra-temporal phenomenon: that is, one that is essentially attained by means of a temporal process of discovery or construction that is continued, in each case, only finitely far. Admittedly, this leads to what are from the alternative, formalist standpoint, severe limitations on the availability of infinite totalities. For instance, there is no sense in speaking of the totality of all number-series or indeed of most non-denumerable infinite sets, and proof by reductio is not generally available.63 However, Becker sees the formalist standpoint itself as problematic in that, with its countenancing of infinite totalities on the slender basis of their formal non-contradictoriness (rather than their actual demonstration in intuition) it creates a kind of “strange” and mysterious “third realm” of objectivities, situated between existence and non-existence (in the concrete, intuitive sense).64 Since the formalist demonstration does not actually consist in concretely exhibiting the relevant entities in present intuition, but merely showing their logical non-contradictoriness, Becker concludes that the formalist can provide, at most, a “logic of consequence” that in fact falls short of an actual “logic of truth” that would provide the entities themselves in their comprehensible givenness.

This posing of the terms of the dispute raises in a sharpened fashion the question of how the infinite and transfinite are themselves intuitively and temporally presentable (if, indeed, they are at all). To address it, Becker develops the implications of Cantor’s own conception of the hierarchy of transfinite sets. As early as 1883, Cantor had conceived of the sets beyond the finite as forming an ordered series of actually existing infinite wholes, while at the same time categorically denying the possibility of any determination of the “absolute” or unincreasable infinity, which he identified with God. In particular, Cantor initially thought of the transfinite hierarchy as generated by means of two “generation principles,” which Becker interrogates as to their ontological significance, in close connection with the phenomenological/ontological idea of the infinite “horizon”, as it had already been developed by Husserl, which makes available the “mastery of the infinite by means of a finite ‘thought’” .65 In the horizon as thought by Husserl, specifically, the “and so on…” of an unlimited possible continuation is nevertheless surveyable in a single, finite “look”, thereby making possible a certain “mastery of the infinite by means of a finite ‘thought’”. 66 The first principle is that, to a present, already formed number, it is always possible to produce a new number by adding one; this is the familiar basis for counting with finite whole numbers, which Cantor extends as well beyond the domain of the finite. It is the second principle, however, which is decisive in producing the transfinite cardinals. According to this second principle, it is possible in general to pass from one’s grasp of the law governing the creation of a particular unlimited series to the formation of a new number which is thought of as succeeding all of the numbers in the series; thus, for instance, the regularity of the sequence of natural numbers 1,2,3,4… engenders the first infinite number, ω.67

Cantor’s own development of the implications of the two principles already suffices to raise two significant questions about the existence and givenness of the transfinite realm of ordinals thereby demonstrated. First, it becomes possible to ask whether there is any possible presentation of the totality of the ordinals: that is, whether the whole realm of the transfinite ordinals can be captured in a single, ‘maximal’ ordinal, W. Second, there is the broader question of whether and how the unlimited progression through the transfinite can actually be motivated or given in concrete experience itself. As Becker notes, the first question is apparently resolved negatively by the antinomy demonstrated by Burali-Forti in 1897 (and closely related to Russell’s paradox of the set of all non-self-membered sets). Because of this antinomy, which shows that such a “maximal” ordinal, if it were to exist, would be both smaller and larger than itself, it must be impossible to suppose the “absolute” infinite W to exist as the limit of all (finite as well as transfinite) counting and limit-processes.68 Becker sees in this circumstance an inherent complication in the transfinite process of generation itself, which in turn provides the occasion for the re-introduction of a certain element of “freedom” and temporal futurity into the concrete generation of the transfinite and the dynamic structure that supports it. For whereas the procedure to ever-higher levels within the transfinite hierarchy is governed, in accordance with Cantor’s second generation principle, by the recurrent passage to the limit that is permitted, in each case, by the specification of a series-law, In the case of the (paradoxical) ordinal W, there is no particular series-law which can support such a passage. In the ordered series of transfinite cardinals, each successive series-law builds on earlier ones, but the process as a whole is therefore “in no sense ever given in its completeness;” rather it must be “always grasped in becoming (dunamei on).”69 This ongoing and essentially open temporal becoming at successive levels is such, Becker argues, as to always again demand what is genuinely a new and creative formation, one that is not mechanically determined at the level below.

To address the second question, Becker draws on the phenomenology of presentation developed by Husserl as well as Heidegger’s radicalization of it on the ground of its ultimate basis in Dasein’s factical life. What is decisive in each case, according to Becker, is the structure of actual concrete reflection through which particular contents or meanings, once attained, can be reflectively modified and transformed into others at “higher” levels: here, the possibility of such iterated reflection is seen as corresponding to the two Cantorian generation principles in allowing for the actual motivation and concrete presentation of ever-higher indices and types. As Becker notes, Husserl, in Ideas I, had already discussed what he called the “step-characteristic” arising from iterated reflection on experience. This is, in particular, a kind of “index” that phenomenologically marks the levels of reflection, reflection on reflection, etc.70 Though Husserl himself develops this possibility of iteration only up to indefinitely high finite levels and situates the whole process of reflective iteration within consciousness rather than concrete, factical life, it is nevertheless in fact possible, Becker argues, to develop from it an “actually living motivation” for a particular type of iteration of reflection which can be conceived as continuing up to the transfinite level.71

Becker considers Karl Löwith’s development of an existentially motivated kind of reflection, which Löwith finds exemplified in Dostoevsky’s “Notes from the Underground” and calls the “parentheses reflection” [Parenthesen-Reflexion].72 Dostoevsky’s work presents the self-dialogue of a fallen man who considers himself and his life as he has factically lived it. This reflection is fruitless and self-defeating; at a certain point, however, “just this fact,” i.e. the fact that he can and does reflect on his life (even in this unfruitful and self-defeating way) itself becomes a theme for reflection. And even this fact can itself become a theme for further reflection, and so on. In this whole process, the infinitely extensible reflection is thus motivated concretely by the impulse to “flee the groundlessness and nullity of one’s own Dasein and to find an inner stability by means of sincere, unsparing self-examination.”73 Moreover, one can in fact recognize in the very course of the reflection that this impulse to take “flight” before facticity has no end. In and by this recognition, according to Becker, the impulse to flight itself, which motivates the whole process, attains an appreciation of its own capability of being continued in infinitum and thereby drives “out over the infinite” [über das Unendliche hinaus] altogether. Thus, if the initial iterative reflection corresponds to the simple iteration of levels that is captured in Cantor’s first generation principle, the second step, wherein the infinite iterability of the initial reflection and its entire containment within one’s own facticity itself is recognized, corresponds to the “passage” to the infinite limit, which is formulated in the second. This consciousness of the possibility of unlimited, univocal iteration through all finite steps is thus, according to Becker, itself the ωth step, and it is now possible to continue to the ω+1st, etc. In this way the givenness of the infinite receives structural motivation from the concrete possibilities of factically experienced life, and “one actually finds…a way from concrete, ‘historical’ life-motivations to a transfinite iteration of reflection.”74

This description of the phenomenon gains further support from Emil Lask’s phenomenological description of the distinction between particular contents and the categorial forms that “encompass” them.75 For Lask, the relationship of form to content, which allows all determinations of “validity,” is analogous to a “clothing” of material with form. This process of clothing can be iterated in reflection or in iterated validity-judgments, and it thus becomes possible that, in this iterated process, the univocity of the concrete steps of iteration is recognized.76 The possibility of this kind of awareness is in fact already implicit, Becker suggests, in the ideas of the horizon and the step-characteristic developed by Husserl in his description of phenomenological reflection. But with Lowith’s parentheses-reflection, Lask’s iteration of validity judgments, and the general possibility of grasping the standing possibility of iterating reflection on one’s concrete life-situation, one gains, according to Becker, a structural motivation for the actual availability of the transfinite that is not merely “epistemological” but actually concretely rooted in the ontological structure of factical life itself.

Becker sees the transfinite structure of reflection, as thereby developed on the basis of the concrete structure of Dasein, as intimately linked to the connected issues of time, decision, and finitude. Given the structure thus illuminated, for instance, it is possible to consider the implications for Hilbert’s decision question, which had been posed some years before, but was still unresolved at the time of Becker’s writing: that is, the question of the existence of problems that are not capable of solution by means of any finite procedure. On Becker’s interpretation, the problem is a “specifically human” one, or is at any rate only “a problem for a ‘finite’ nature (a ‘creature’).”77 In particular, the problem arises only for a being which is essentially bounded in time and would not, therefore, arise for a being capable of “intellectual intuition” or God, who (according to Becker) “does not need to count.”78 This verifies, according to Becker, that both number and the problem of mathematical objectivity, if treated in terms of it concrete factical condition, more generally must be “referred back to time,” and thereby to what can be treated as a “specific human form of intuition,” as it is in Kant.79

Becker sees in the concretely motivated structure of transfinite reflection and its relation to finite temporality grounds for an actual resolution of the intuitionism/formalism dispute in favor of (a non-finitist form of) intuitionism. For according to Becker, given this thoroughgoing temporal conditioning of mathematical existence, the actual demonstration of mathematical objectivity must be accomplished, in each case, by means of an actual carrying-out of the relevant construction or synthesis which displays the object itself. By contrast with the formalist “demonstration” by means of a proof of noncontradictoriness, this carrying-out of actual processes of construction or synthesis guarantees that the specific “being-sense” (i.e. the meaning of the being) of the relevant mathematical objects, including the transfinite ordinals, remains in view and that they thereby maintain their foundation in factical, concrete life. More broadly, Becker sees this outcome as deciding in favor of an “anthropological” conception of mathematical knowledge in general, which he contrasts with the “absolute” one according to which the mathematical domain is a “measuredly structured universum” existing in itself.80 Instead of having such an extra-human and atemporal mode of existence, in particular, mathematics is here to be seen as having an “anthropological” foundation in the “factical life of humans, the “the in-each-case-one’s-own [jeweils eigene] life of the individual (or at least the occurrent [jeweiligen] “generation”).”81 In particular, the concrete motivation of the transfinite progression on the basis of Dasein’s factical life and temporality motivates the idea of a “progress” into the future which is no longer understandable on the basis of an eternally existing substrate of present moments, each one in principle the same as the last, but rather as an irreducibly dynamic process of open, reflexive becoming, which Becker designates, adopting Heidegger’s terminology, as “historical temporality.”82 This temporality is further, according to Becker, to be seen as connected or identical to the “authentic” or primordial time that had already been described by Heidegger as the reflexive structure of Dasein through which Dasein “gives itself its time” and is in a certain way “time itself.”83

This provides a basis on which Becker can clarify the contrasting sense in which an interpretation of time figures in classical analysis and in the foundations of the traditional conception of the realm of the mathematical as the eternal or extra-temporal. In particular, Becker here suggests that the traditional determination of the infinite or apeiron in terms of the character of an unlimited temporal repetition of the same provides a basic structure that underlies or produces the overall conception of time as such.84 As Becker argues, the basic character in the conception of the infinite as potential which ultimately yields Aristotle’s understanding of time as the number of motion may be seen as having even deeper roots, before Plato, in the thinking of the Pythagorean Archytas, as well as the pre-socratics Anaxagoras, Zeno, and finally Anaximander.85 In each of these thinkers, according to Becker, the question of time indeed already played “a decisive role in the definition of the apeiron.”86 For Archytas and, before him, Anaxagoras, the existence of space and entities already had, in itself, the character of the aei, or “always”, of eternity.87 We can, according to Becker, apparently trace to Zeno the first clear understanding of this aei as implying the infinite repeatability, in principle, of the individual instance, as well as the idea of the infinite divisibility of continua of motion and space which yields his notorious paradoxes of motion.88 And before all of these, Anaximander understood the principle (or arche) of things as the apeiron, or the unlimited, holding (in what may be the first direct quotation that reaches us from the pre-Socratics) that:


Where their arising is from, therein arises also their strife, according to necessity. For they count against one another strife and compensation according to the ordinance of time.89

According to Becker, we can already see in this the origin of the conception of time which dominates Greek thought, a conception of time as the eternal and infinite rhythmic alteration or repetition. Here, “apeiron is the original power … that becoming never allows to cease.” In this respect, according to Becker, the Anaximander fragment already yields the prototype for the interlinked conception of the infinite and time that comes to the fore in Aristotle’s developed conception of time as the number of motion.

But if there is a basic sense in which the thought of time is always determined for the Greeks, including Plato, on the basis of the thought of the aei as eternal repetition in presence of the same, this thought is nevertheless undermined in a decisive and internal way by certain problematic discoveries of Greek mathematics, already well known to Plato himself, which arise again in a different form in the contemporary (20th century) context of the intuitionist-formalist debate itself. In particular, as Becker notes, the contemporary problem of the continuum, as it has been developed by Cantor in terms of his method of diagonalization and his conception of continua as point sets, is itself closely related to the problem that appeared already in the problem of the nature and definition of irrational magnitudes for the Greeks, where it already played a crucial methodological and philosophical role in their thinking about number, magnitude, and the infinite. On Becker’s reading, the critical problem posed by the discovery of irrational magnitudes such as that of the diagonal of a unit square, in particular, seemed to Plato and others of his time to pose a deep threat to “the thoroughgoing rule of form, of ordering principles [des ordnenden Prinzips], and indeed not only in the realm of sensory, fluctuating becoming [des sinnlichen, flieβenden Werdens], but even in that of precisely construable beings (those that can be ascertained by dianoia) [in dem des exakt konstruierbaren (mittels den dianoia erfaβbaren) Seienden].”90 This prompted mathematicians such as Euclid and, before him, (the historical) Theaetetus to undertake a rigorous and exhaustive construction and classification of the forms of irrational magnitudes themselves.91 The attempt sufficed partially to overcome the crisis posed by the initial discovery of the irrational, but only by means of a piecemeal and essentially partial re-incorporation of its structure back into the realm of classifiable and surveyable relations. Nevertheless, as Becker argues, their remained in Plato’s own thought the decisive sense of a primary apeiron which structurally insists in the actual genesis of number and indicates therein the inherent moment of an unlimited becoming that threatens to outstrip determinate limits, boundaries and order. This is, specifically, the late-Platonic conception of the aoristos duas or ‘unlimited dyad,’ which was, according to the suggestion of Aristotle’s own polemics against the Platonic conception, at the origin and root of the generation of number in its combination with the contrastive principle of the one or the limit.

Becker discusses the progression from Plato’s conception of number to Aristotle’s in terms of what he sees as the development from an anciently rooted and mystical conception of number as figure to the conception decisive in Aristotle’s thinking and indeed in all subsequent mathematical investigations into number and the continuum, that of number as seriality and order.92 On the initial, “mystical” conception, still present in Plato, number is a kind of figure that gives the possibility of measure (p. 201).93 Here, according to Becker, infinite number is basically unthinkable; for the figural character of numbers is basically understood as its being limited.94 On the other hand, as Aristotle, at any rate, certainly grasped, the conception of number as a position in a series immediately demands the thought of the possibility of an endless procession, one that can be continued indefinitely without running to an end. Becker suggests that Aristotle in fact sees in this endlessness a basic link not only to number and the mathematical, but also, decisively, to the “basic phenomenon of time.”95

Nevertheless, although the “series” character of number and the specific phenomenon of the potential infinite involved in it only becomes fully explicit with Aristotle, Becker already sees in the late Plato’s conception of the aoristos duas a significant development of it, whereby it is methodologically linked, according to Becker, with the distinctive methodology of synthesis and diaeresis suggested in dialogues such as the Sophist, the Statesman, and the Philebus. In particular, Becker, following Stenzel, suggests that Plato here contemplates a synthetic/diaeretic development of numbers, whereby they are generated through a repeated process of “something like doubling and halving.”96 Through this process, in particular, “whole numbers as well as fractions originate through the genetic possibility of the aoristos duas (the unlimited dyad).”97 The dyad, developing the implications of the apeiron itself as irreducibly “something becoming [eines Werdenden]” thereby amounts to the ultimate “potency generative of number [die zahlen erzeugende Potenz] (duopoios) .98 In the repeated possibility of division that it introduces, it thus, when balanced with the equally basic principle of the unifying, synthetic one or limit, provides an essentially unlimited arche or dunamis capable not only of structuring the whole unlimited domain of (whole and fractional) numbers but also explaining their ultimate structural genesis.



In a later (1931) article “The Diairetic Generation of Platonic Ideal Numbers,” Becker further develops the suggestion that the generation of numbers can be considered to be an outcome of the late-Platonic structure of diaeresis, and indeed actually identical to that of the diairetic definition of a concept by division. Here, Becker suggests in particular that ideal numbers can be seen as generated by a repeated process whereby one divides into two, but in the division the original one is “sublated” or overcome in the division.99 The seriality of number can thus be seen as generated in a way that is “formally identical” to the structure of the diairesis of concepts that Plato suggests in the Sophist and the Statesman. According to the solution, what corresponds to the diairetically disclosed “parts” of a defined concept in the ideal number is not the number itself but its “units.”100 In this way the formal structure of the decomposition of the idea in the definition is exactly formally analogous to the generation of the number. Becker also notes the possibility of connecting this to the structure of the division of a continuous quantity by iterated fractional decomposition to produce an exact (rational) point.101 In this way, he suggests, the process of diairesis which results in the identification of the constituents of an idea as “monads” or “ones” may be thought to produce examples of the sort that Plato appeals to in the Sophist, the Philebus, and other late texts, e.g. the identification of the fixed letters or discrete musical notes from the fluid continuum of possible sounds.102


  1. Download 209.01 Kb.

    Share with your friends:
1   2   3   4   5




The database is protected by copyright ©ininet.org 2024
send message

    Main page