The Over-extended Mind David Cole umd



Download 33.66 Kb.
Date31.07.2017
Size33.66 Kb.
#25939
The Over-extended Mind

David Cole UMD

[3225 words Sept 28 2010 + references
Are you smarter than a Fifth Grader? OK, well how about a Fifth grader with G4 mobile high-speed internet access??
There’s a possibly more interesting general question: does technology transform and extend the mind and our mental powers? In a widely discussed 1998 paper titled “The Extended Mind”, Andy Clark and David Chalmers argue that mind and cognition can extend outside the head and can include items and processes in the world. In their thought experiment, Otto has alzheimer’s syndrome but does not lose his ability to function because he records information he learns in a notebook that he always carries. Thus, C&C claim, Otto continues to have beliefs. The notebooks function as his memory. C&C propose a "parity principle": a part of the world is part of a cognitive process if it "functions as a process which, were it done in the head, we would have no hesitation in recognizing [it] as part of the cognitive process .... Cognitive processes ain't (all) in the head!" (in Menary p. 29, original emphasis).

The Extended Mind (EM) movement is part of a large clash of approachs to understanding mind and cognition. On the classic Representational Theory of Mind, sensory processes bring information into the head, these produce representations in the brain, neural processes produce cognitive operations such as inferences including practical reasoning that results in intentions to behave, and this output controls behavior, including linguistic behavior. Regarding language, in particular, linguistic input is translated into Mentalese, mentalese reps are processed, and the result is translated back into representations of natural language, resulting in speech or writing. All cognition is inside the head. This clashes with EM, aka embodied or embedded cognition, which sees the environment as often a component of cognition. In particular, devices such as an abacus or a computer, and natural languages are seen as extenders of cognition and mind. Finally, Radical Embodied Cognition (e.g. Chemero 2009) dispenses with representations whether inside or outside the mind and sees the mind as coupled with the environment to form a single dynamic system that functions without the need for representations. I’ll focus here on EM and its direct critics.

Clark has gone on to defend and extend the extended mind thesis in his 2008 book _SuperSizing the Mind_. The Extended Mind claim has been controversial, and many (e.g. Jerry Fodor, no surprise) think it is unacceptable. It is easy to understand the tension. On the one hand, we have long used various tools when thinking, including books, pen and paper, abacus and calculator, and have always distinguished between the tool and the mind that uses them. On the other hand, the EM claim seems a relatively straight-forward consequence of functionalism, the position that what makes something a mental state or process is the causal role it plays. Functionalism was designed to counter substance chauvinism (e.g. pain must involve activation of particular neurons); why isn’t requiring a particular location for cognitive processes, namely confined to the cranium, just location chauvinism? And if to the question “Do you know what time it is” I can rightly answer “yes”, then glance at my watch, and say “4:30”, it seems I often attribute to myself knowledge that I have only in virtue of interaction with an artifact. The external watch becomes an essential component of my self-ascribed state of knowledge. So what then can be the difference between merely using a cognitive tool and extending one’s mind?

For starters, one must be causally coupled with the tool, but that by itself is not sufficient. Chalmers and Clark propose three conditions for a coupling to count as constitutive of cognition: information in the resource must be 1) reliably available and used, 2) automatically endorsed, and 3) easily accessible.  The second condition is meant to rule out e.g. mobile access to Google, as in our 5th grader example - but, as near as I can tell, it would not rule out mobile access to self-authored Google-docs or diary entries. Nor does it rule out the watch example, assuming my watch is virtually always with me and I generally unreflectingly rely on it and endorse its time indications. So Extended Mind thesis is not just about exotic technology; it appears to entail that Otto’s mind includes his notebooks, and, moving from thought-experiment to the real world, that my mind includes my watch and the things-to-do list in my pocket.

I think there are important insights, perhaps of focus, that come from the extended mind approach, but I don’t think we have discovered that our minds are partly on our wrists or in our cell phones or pockets. Rather I’ll argue that just as we have a pretty good distinction between our bodies and our cars and hammers, we have a good distinction between our minds and the information tools with which they couple. At the same time, I think we can hold that our minds can be parts of larger cognitive processes that include cognitive tools. Building a house is a task that involves bodies and tools; designing the building is a cognitive task that involves minds and tools. The extended mind thesis holds that we must include as part of the mind anything which, if it were in the head, we would count as part of a cognitive process. But clearly we don’t do this with the physical – I am not required to count as part of my body anything such that if it were inside my body would be counted as a bodily part. If I am on an artificial kidney machine, even though the process of blood cleansing is the same that would count as a bodily process were my body doing it, the dialysis machine is not a part of my body. Buying a Subaru Outback is not body-building. In general, being coupled to a machine does not make the machine part of my body.

So the modest proposal comes down to continuing to draw the mind/world boundary where we have done, but recognize the important ways in which cognitive processes can extend beyond our skin. Thus we can reject an identity of our minds with all the cognitive processes in which we are involved. Some cognitive processes take place entirely inside our heads and minds, and are purely mental, and some do not.



An abacus can be part of cognitive processes. I am particularly interested in the way in which crucial aspects of partly external cognitive processes can be brought inside the head. Japanese abacus students can be speed-drilled to operate an abacus very rapidly. After extensive training, the abacus can be removed. The students stare into space and their fingers twitch and they come up with the right answers. They calculate as if they were using a physical abacus, but it is all mental. Thus cognitive processes can change from being extended to being entirely mental, in the head. This is, it seems to me, a very important change. But if we count our mind as including all the external props, then it appears the abacus savants have contracted their minds by losing a conspicuous component, the actual physical abacus. Surely it is more reasonable to think of them as having enhanced mental abilities. Solving math problems is cognitive, whether the process involves external artifacts or not. But mental arithmetic is entirely inside the mind and is an importantly distinct phenomenon, and one that is more difficult to master for most of us.
The lead critics of Extended Mind, Fred Adams and Ken Aizawa, have focused largely on other issues. First, they despair whether the disparate phenomena (notebooks, watches, pen and paper) that could be part of mind on the C&C EM view could constitute a unified science of cognition. Clark has replied to this, I think adequately. However A&A have mostly emphasized two more objections to EM: the Extended Mind argument commits a “coupling-constitution fallacy”: it is one thing to use a tool, especially a cognitive tool such as a calculator, and another for the tool to literally be a part of one's thought. Third, they argue that external states (such as the inscriptions in Otto's notebook) and devices lack the "intrinsic" content possessed by brain states, and it is this intrinsic or original content that is requisite for components of true cognition.  (The latter point is stressed by Fodor in a recent review of Clark 2008 as the decisive refutation.)  The critic's idea is that the content (or "intentionality") of external stuff depends on the minds that create and interpret, but not vice versa.  Brain states have intrinsic intentionality, states of notebooks, calculators and iPads have derived intentionality.
Some of you may have noticed that similar considerations play a role in Searle's Chinese Room argument. My suspicion is that if you like the Chinese Room argument, you are likely to be sympathetic to this criticism of extended mind; if not, not. EM bears on Searle’s Chinese Room argument in other ways besides raising issues of intentionality, they also bear on the identity and boundaries of minds: do the manuals and scratchpads in the Chinese Room extend Searle's mind so that he understands Chinese? The Systems Reply says No, the entity that understands is the system, not the system operator. Searle says in reply that he could internalize the manuals and scratchpads of the system and that he still wouldn’t understand Chinese. I have agreed with Searle on that narrow point, but have gone on to argue that in either case, whether he runs the program using external manuals and scratchpads, or entirely inside his head, he could be producing a distinct person from himself that might understand Chinese even if he didn’t. Thus I suggest these matters are complicated – the boundary of head and world is not always the same as the distinction between my mind and world, and if one manipulates external representations and thereby produces cognitive processes, this does not in itself guarantee that those are one’s own cognitive processes. Production and ownership are distinct.

Along the lines suggested here, in thinking about A&A’s coupling-constitution criticism, I think we need to make the distinction between mind and cognitive process. On this view, contary to A&A it is not a fallacy to hold that when we causally couple with things and processes in the external environment these come to constitute – be part of – our cognitive processes. On the other hand, it is a mistake to think that these come to be parts of our minds. So the distinction between mind and cognitive process is crucial, on the view I am advocating here, and marks the boundary between fallacy and interesting idea and research program.



With regard to the third objection that A&A (and Fodor) press, I am not at all convinced by the claim that brain states have original intentionality and notebook entries do not. A full treatment of this cannot be given here (but see

www.d.umn.edu/~dcole/Against.Derived.Intentionality.doc). The short of it is that critical examination of the arguments for the distinction itself reveals it is problematic. Furthermore, if entries in Otto’s notebooks, say of addresses and directions to landmarks are entirely or include printouts of computer generated directions based on aerial photographs, so that no representation mirrors any representation that was ever in anyone’s head, then, it seems to me, the marks have original intentionality and in an obvious sense the states in Otto’s mind when he reads them have derived intentionality. They depend on the intentionality of the machine generated entries. Thus original and derived don’t necessarily conincide with a mind artifact boundary.
Counterexamples to Extended Mind thesis:
So perhaps the rejection of the extended mind thesis should not rest on an appeal to intrinsic intentionality. There are several other reasons for being suspicious of the position. Suppose, e.g., I transcribed a 1962 Buick Shop Manual as part of a summer job years ago. The contents went through my head, and I believed ("endorsed") everything the manual said, but I have forgotten it all now. But if I am holding the manual, then according to C and C, it seems I have an extended mind and know things that are in the manual. But if I know what is in the manual, then I have not forgotten what is in the manual. This is a contradiction.
Perhaps one might thin that since I got credit for accomplishing my successful cognitive tasks, such as math calculations (“I did my own taxes”) and knowing the time, the consituents of the processes must all be constituents of my mind as well. Thus I will not be able to embrace extended cognition while rejecting extended mind.
Books and language are cognitive tools. So it is useful to compare how we think about other, ordinary non-cognitive, tools. A roofer can nail shingles, using a hammer. We give the roofer credit for the accomplishment of the job. Still, we do not think of the hammer as part of the roofer. It is true that the hammer acts as if it were a temporary extension of the roofer’s hand. And it is true that a mutant roofer could have been born with a hammerhand. Still, in the case of an ordinary roofer using a hammer, we do not treat the hammer as part of the roofer, as an "extended hand". It is _as if_ the hand were extended, but it is not literally an extended hand with a hardened end; he is not Edward Hammerhands. We have the usual important difference between "as if" and "is".
Perceptual aids are closer to cognitive extensions. We hear friends speak, by using a phone. We see mars, using a telescope. We can imagine a superhero with x-ray or telescopic vision, or extended hearing. We are somewhat like such superheroes when we use technology, even something as simple as an earhorn, to aid perception. But there is an important difference between a superhero and us. The phone is an aid, not a part of you. Your ear does not extend into the phone. Your eye does not extend when you hold a telescope in front of it.
But it is true that you can see further with the telescope - your perception is extended. I can see features on Mars with a telescope, but not with the naked eye. My reach can be extended if I stand on a box. Thus it seems some things, including cognitive processes such as perception, can be extended and others can't. Is a mind among the things that can be extended?
I think it is useful at this point to introduce some empirical considerations, and considerations of personal identity. Some cases of interest are cooperative or social cognitive activity, dicephalous twins, split-brain subjects, and savants. I would suggest that these are on a continuum with normal subjects.
First, If you and I work together and solve a problem that neither of us could solve alone, it does not mean that either got his mind extended. People and tools assist us in our tasks, but they don't increase our size by literally extending us. In the case of mind, it seems even less plausible to treat the use of external aids as extensions of the mind, and to treat the mind as including the aids.
The articulate British Savant Daniel Tammet, who has recited the decimal expansion of pi to over 22,000 digits, reports that he "reads" the digits off of a changing mental colored visual image that reveals each digit to him. As I understand the phenomenology, he is not aware of the processes that create the image. Thus it appears that "one part of his mind" generates the numbers, and communicates with his conscious language capable mind via visual imagery. Now clearly there is a huge difference between this unique phenomenon, and someone who used a computer that generated the digits of pi and displayed them as changing colored shape images on a computer screen. The latter cannot generate the expansion mentally, whereas Tammet can. Thus it seems wrong to treat the latter as having an extended mind. The _bottom line_ is the same of course - both generate the decimal expansion. If one were hiring a pi expert, one might be indifferent. But we are interested in mental abilities here, and it is clear that Tammet has unusual mental abilities - which would not be the case if an ordinary bloke by using a computer literally extended his mind so as to have the very same mental abilities. Mental arithmetic is just in the head.
Split brain subjects pose a problem, for experimental evidence suggests that they are in some ways like having two minds in a single subject. As soon as two complete brains are present, both with language control, even though the body is one, most have no qualms in treating the case as one of two minds. Minnesota’s own Hensel twins, Abigail and Brittany, are two of a handful of surviving human dicephalous twins. These two share a body and finish each other’s sentences. Producing a sentence is a shared cognitive task. And together they ride bikes and drive cars. But it is clear there are two personalities and two minds, however tightly coupled they may be. Cognitive processes are cooperative and extended, but minds don’t divide the same way.
Since we don't think of normal twins as constituting a single mind, even if they work together as a project and are very like-minded – including endorsing each other's beliefs - it seems C&C’s conditions – omnipresence and readily endorsed – are not sufficient for making something part of my mind. Perhaps then the distinction between minds comes with the _possibility_ of separate thoughts. If one twin were the permanent mental slave of the other and silent (except, perhaps, for the occasional Freudian slip), then perhaps the silent twin would be more like the silent hemisphere in normal brains and we could regard the twin-team as constituting a single mind.
A related suggestion might be that in a group that endorses each others' beliefs, there is still the _possibility_ of rejecting. It is that possibility that is the sign of multiple minds. As intuitive as this may seem, it immediately runs into a problem - I may reject the "evidence of my own eyes" - the dispositions to believe proffered by my visual system - on the basis of cognitive information. This doesn't multiply minds. So even actual failure to endorse the results of a cognitive subsystem does not affect mind count, and so it seems endorsing can't be an essential factor in making a single mind, contra C and C's suggestion.

Blindsight and multiple personality disorders are also related phenomena - blindsight is perhaps best described as a single mind with internal communication problems. Hallucinating Schizophrenics and Multiple personality disorder is difficult to categorize - extreme cases might be treated as single body/ multiple minds. In the case of MPD, perhaps it would depend on what information the "personalities" share.


Perhaps there is a key component of mind count, and that is center of consciousness and control. Thus _I_ have the last say on whether to accept the deliverances of my visual system, and the "I" that has this say is conscious of both the deliverances and the power to reject. This is all very Cartesian. But if it is correct, my mind, the locus of thought, is distinct from the tools it uses, and is not extended by the addition of tools, while its capabilities may be. The analogy is with someone who controls heavy construction equipment using a joystick - he guy is not any bigger, but he can accomplish greater physical tasks using the heavy equipment. It is _as if_ he were extended, but that is not to be extended. So I think that at best C and C give us cases where it is as if minds were extended, but not cases where it is compelling to say they are actually extended outside the head.
The problems and objections II have raised don’t apply to cognitive processes that complete cognitive tasks. So I conclude that it is reasonable to hold that my mind is not identical with the sum of the cognitive processes in which it engages.
I began with the question, does technology transform and extend the mind and our cognitive processes? In the subsequent discussion I have argued that we should split this complex question. It seems clear that technology and external systems such as language extend our cognitive powers, enabling us to figure out things and solve cognitive problems that would have been forever beyond our ken and understanding. It is also reasonable to hold that persistent interaction with these external technologies and representation systems probably transforms our brains and minds in many interesting and important ways. But at the same time we can reasonably hold that technology does not extend our minds outside our heads.
References:
Adams, R and Aizawa, K. in Menary 2010.
Chemero, A. 2009 Radical Embodied Cognitive Science MIT Press
Clark, A 2008 Supersizing the Mind: Embodiment, Action and Cognitive Extension. Oxford University Press.
Clark, A. in Menary 2010.
Clark and Chalmers, D 1998 “Extending the Mind” Analysis
Cole, D review of Clark Supersizing the Mind in Minds and Machines
Cole, D. review of Chemero 2009 in Minds and Machines
Cole, D. 2010 “Against Derived Intentionality” www.d.umn.edu/~dcole/Against.Derived.Intentionality.doc
Fodor, J. 2009 “Where is my Mind?” review of Clark 2008 London Review of Books Vol 38 n.3 pp. 13-15. http://www.lrb.co.uk/v31/n03/jerry-fodor/where-is-my-mind
Menary, R. 2010 The Extended Mind MIT Press
Download 33.66 Kb.

Share with your friends:




The database is protected by copyright ©ininet.org 2024
send message

    Main page