Planet Debate 2011 September/October l-d release Animal Rights


Duty Toward Animals in Captivity Different from Those in the Wild



Download 1.43 Mb.
Page16/133
Date16.08.2017
Size1.43 Mb.
#33284
1   ...   12   13   14   15   16   17   18   19   ...   133

Duty Toward Animals in Captivity Different from Those in the Wild


DUTIES TO ANIMALS IN HUMAN CAPTIVITY DIFFERENT THAN THOSE TO WILD ANIMALS

Bryan G. Norton, professor of philosophy, science and technology, School of Public Policy, Georgia Institute of Technology, 2003, Searching for Sustainability: interdisciplinary essays in the philosophy of conservation biology, p. 388

In the wild, we only express our awe at the power and cruelty of nature, and we avoid intervening whenever possible. But once the individual animal is brought by us into the human community, new constraints are imposed upon human treatment of individuals – we have taken responsibility for the animal’s well-being. The humans in question have therefore committed themselves to act as responsible stewards for the now helpless animals, and they must devise a new ethic appropriate to this different situation.

This line of reasoning explains the gravity of our decision to remove wild animals from the wild; it also explains the seriousness of the responsibilities we come to owe individuals once we become their moral guardians. Sometimes this responsibility is thrust upon us, as when a baby animal is orphaned as an unforeseen outcome of human activities; at other times, we grasp this responsibility, recognizing that a given species, which we value, is threatened and that extraordinary interventions are necessary to prevent permanent rents in the fabric of natural systems. In either case we must act responsibly, recognizing to the extent possible the impacts our actions will have on individual lives, and recognizing also the gravity of the situation.




Justifications for Rigid Species Barrier Wrong


BELIEF IN RIGID BARRIERS BETWEEN HUMANS AND NON-HUMANS GROUNDED IN FANTASIES MASQUERADING AS TRUTH

Stephen R. L. Clark, professor of philosophy at Liverpool University, 1994, The Great Ape Project: equality beyond humanity, eds. Cavalieri & Singer, p. 122-3

I said before that either we are simply natural products of evolutionary processes or we are not. If we are, then it seems clear that there are no rigid boundaries between species groups, that species, and other taxa, are quite real, but only as Realgattungen. There is a real difficulty, however, in believing this, despite the efforts made by other contributors to this very volume to expound a fully naturalized epistemology. The argument, which is a powerful one even if it has not convinced all theorists, runs as follows. If we are the products of evolutionary processes, then we have no good ground for thinking that our thoughts are anything but none-too-harmful fantasies. As Nietzsche saw, we must presume that we have evolved as the descendants of creatures who could ignore a lot, who could live out their fantasies. There is nothing in evolutionary epistemology to give us reason to expect that we would care about the abstract truth, or ever be able to obtain it. If the theory is correct, we have no reason to think that we could find out any correct theories, beyond (at best) such truths or falsehoods as we need to obtain the next meal or avoid being one. And so we have no reason to suppose that any theory that we have devised is really true, including the current theory of evolution. Only if the divine reason is somehow present in us can we expect that we would find our truths, or trust our moral instincts. That, after all, was what Enlightenment thinkers thought, borrowing a Platonic doctrine about the powers of reason that does not fit the neo-Aristotelian framework I have so far described.

This alternative picture—that evolutionary theory does not leave room for the kind of being we have to think we are (namely truth-seeking and would-be moral images of a divine reason)—is what has often lain behind attempts to insist upon a radical disjunction between apes and people. But there is a better answer. Plato, after all, denied that it was sensible to contrast human and nonhuman things, creatures of our specific kind and all others. We might as well divide the universe into cranes and noncranes. By his account (or at least the account developed from his writings), there are indeed real natures, but they are not identical with the things that partly remind us of them. Even we ourselves are not wholly identical with the Form of Humanity, though we are called to serve it. The Form of Humanity, is the divine reason, and we are indeed more human, in this sense, insofar as we think and do as the divine reason requires. The true image of humanity, for us, is the saint or perfect sage.
POPULARITY OF BELIEF IN HUMAN MORAL SUPERIORITY DOESN’T MAKE IT RIGHT

Peter Singer, Professor of Bioethics, Princeton, 2004, Animal Rights: Current debates and new directions, eds. Sunstein & Nussbaum, p. 78-9

Most people draw a sharp moral line between humans and other animals. Humans, they say, are infinitely more valuable than any “lower creatures.” If our interests conflict with those of animals, it is always their interests which should be sacrificed. But why should this be so? To say that everyone believes this is not enough to justify it. Until very recently it was the common view that a woman should obey her father, until she is married, and then her husband (and in some countries, this is still the prevailing view). Or, not quite so recently, but still not all that long ago, it was widely held that people of African descent could properly be enslaved. As these examples show, the fact that a view is widespread does not make it right. It may be an indefensible prejudice that survives primarily because it suits the interests of the dominant group.

Justifications for Rigid Species Barrier Wrong



IRRATIONAL TO DRAW THE LINE AT MORAL CONSIDERATION BASED ON HUMAN-LIKE ATTRIBUTES

Gary Francione, Professor of Law, Rutgers, 2004, Animal Rights: Current debates and new directions, eds. Sunstein & Nussbaum, p. 129

First, any attempt to justify treating animals as resources based on their lack of supposed uniquely human characteristics begs the question from the outset by assuming that certain human characteristics are special and justify differential treatment. Even if, for instance, no animals other than humans can recognize themselves in mirrors or can communicate through symbolic language, no human is capable of flying, or breathing underwater, without assistance. What makes the ability to recognize oneself in a mirror or use symbolic language better in a moral sense than the ability to fly or breathe underwater? The answer, of course, is that we say so. But apart from our proclamation, there is simply no reason to conclude that characteristics thought to be uniquely human have any value that allows us to use them as a nonarbitrary justification for treating animals as property. These characteristics can serve this role only after we have assumed their moral relevance.



Download 1.43 Mb.

Share with your friends:
1   ...   12   13   14   15   16   17   18   19   ...   133




The database is protected by copyright ©ininet.org 2024
send message

    Main page