Planet Debate 2011 September/October l-d release Animal Rights


**Answer To: Animals Do Not Deserve Rights**



Download 1.43 Mb.
Page26/133
Date16.08.2017
Size1.43 Mb.
#33284
1   ...   22   23   24   25   26   27   28   29   ...   133

**Answer To: Animals Do Not Deserve Rights**

AT: “Differences Between Humans and Animals Justify Restricting Animal Rights”


NO MORALLY RELEVANT DISTINCTIONS JUSTIFY DISCRIMINATING AGAINST NON-HUMANS

Bernard E. Rollin, professor of philosophy, Colorado State University, 1994, The Great Ape Project: equality beyond humanity, eds. Cavalieri & Singer, p. 209



One major step towards extending the ethic to animals, not difficult for the average person to take, is the realization that there exists no good reason for withholding it: in other words, that there is no morally relevant difference between humans and animals which can rationally justify not assessing the treatment of animals by the machinery of our consensus ethic for humans. Not only are there no morally relevant differences, there are significant morally relevant similarities. Most important, most people believe that animals are conscious beings, that what we do to them matters to them, that they are capable of a wide range of morally relevant experiences—pain, fear, happiness, boredom, joy, sorrow, grief; in short, the full range of feelings which figure so prominently in our moral concern for humans.
RIGHTS” DISCOURSE IMPLIES THE CONCEPT OF LIBERATION – ARGUMENTS THAT ANIMALS LACK ATTRIBUTES FOR RIGHTS IRRELEVANT

Peter Singer, Professor of Philosophy Monash University, 1995, Animal Liberation, p. 8

In misguided attempts to refute the arguments of this book, some philosophers have gone to much trouble development arguments to show that animals do not have rights. They have claimed that to have rights a being must be autonomous, or must be a member of a community, or just have the ability to respect the rights of others, or must possess a sense of justice. These claims are irrelevant to the case for Animal Liberation. The language of rights is a convenient political shorthand. It is even more valuable in the era of thirty-second TV news clips than it was in Bentham’s day; but in the argument for a radical change in our attitude to animals, it is in no way necessary.
JUSTIFYING DISCRIMINATORY TREATMENT ON SUPPOSED “HUMAN” TRAITS RATHER THAN MERE MEMBERSHIP IN THE SPECIES EXCLUDES HUMANS WHO LACK THE TRAITS

Ingmar Persson, professor of philosophy, Lund University, 1994, The Great Ape Project: equality beyond humanity, eds. Cavalieri & Singer, p. 191

But probably, when all is said and done, this is not what speciesism would come down to—just as racism and sexism do not simply amount to the doctrine that certain beings be discriminated against just because of their race or gender. A more intelligent speciesism (racism, sexism) proposes that beings belonging to some species (race, sex) be favored at the expense of beings belonging to other species (races, sexes) due to characteristics typical of these species (races, sexes); for instance, that humans should be better catered for than all nonhuman animals because they alone are rational, have the capacity to speak a language, etc. In other words, the real basis for discrimination is not species membership, but the possession of rationality or some other mental faculty.

Against this sort of speciesism the so-called argument from marginal cases has been marshaled: it is pointed out that if it is the absence of rationality, linguistic ability, etc., that justifies discrimination against nonhuman animals, discrimination against some humans—in particular, those who are severely mentally handicapped—is also justifiable, since they, too, lack the precious qualities. Apparently, normal chimpanzees, gorillas and orang-utans are at least as intelligent as some mentally impaired humans. It does not help the human speciesist that these humans belong to a species that is normally equipped with the mental assets in question, because it is surely more reasonable to treat a being according to the properties it in fact possesses than according to those that make up the norm for some group to which it belongs, regardless of whether or not the individual in question has them.

AT: “Differences Between Humans and Animals Justify Restricting Animal Rights”



BASING MORAL CONSIDERATION ON THE POSSESSION OF “HUMAN” ATTRIBUTES NECESSARILY EXCLUDES SOME HUMANS

Gary Francione, Professor of Law, Rutgers, 2004, Animal Rights: Current debates and new directions, eds. Sunstein & Nussbaum, p. 129-30

Second, even if all animals other than humans lack a particular characteristic beyond sentience, or possess it to a different degree than do humans, there is no logically defensible relationship between the lack or lesser degree of that characteristic and our treatment of animals as resources. Differences between humans and other animals may be relevant for other purposes—no sensible person argues that we ought to enable nonhuman animals to drive cars or vote or attend universities—but the differences have no bearing on whether animals should have the status of property. We recognize this inescapable conclusion where humans are involved. Whatever characteristic we identify as uniquely human will be seen to a lesser degree in some humans and not at all in others. Some humans will have the exact same deficiency that we attribute to animals, and although the deficiency may be relevant for some purposes, most of us would reject enslaving such humans, or otherwise treating such humans exclusively as means to the ends of others.
EVERY UNIQUELY “HUMAN” CHARACTERISTIC OFFERED TO JUSTIFY TREATING ANIMALS AS PROPERTY APPLIES TO SOME HUMAN BEINGS AS WELL

Gary Francione, Professor of Law, Rutgers, 2004, Animal Rights: Current debates and new directions, eds. Sunstein & Nussbaum, p. 130

Consider, for instance, self-consciousness. Peter Carruthers defines self-consciousness as the ability to have a “conscious experience…whose existence and content are available to be consciously thought about (that is, available for description in acts of thinking that are themselves made available to further acts of thinking).” According to Carruthers, humans must have what Damasio refers to as the most complex level of extended consciousness, or a language-enriched autobiographical sense of self, in order to be self-conscious. But many humans, such as the severely mentally disabled, do not have self-consciousness in that sense; we do not, however, regard it as permissible to use them as we do laboratory animals, or to enslave them to labor for those without their particular disability. Nor should we. We recognize that a mentally disabled human has an interest in her life and in not being treated exclusively as a means to the ends of others even if she does not have the same level of self-consciousness that is possessed by normal adults; in this sense, she is similarly situated to all other sentient humans, who have an interest in being treated as ends in themselves, irrespective of their particular characteristics. Indeed, to say that a mentally disabled person is not similarly situated to all others for the purposes of being treated exclusively as a resource is to say that a less intelligent person is not similarly situated to a more intelligent person for purposes of being used, for instance, as a forced organ donor. The fact that the mentally disabled human may not have a particular sort of self-consciousness may serve as a nonarbitrary reason for treating her differently in some respects—it may be relevant to whether we make her the host of a talk show, or giver her a job teaching at a university, or allow her to drive a car—but it has no relevance to whether we treat her exclusively as a resource and disregard her fundamental interests, including her interest in not suffering and in her continued existence, it if benefits us to do so.

The same analysis applies to every human characteristic beyond sentience that is offered to justify treating animals as resources. There will be some humans who also lack this characteristic or possess it to a lesser degree than normal humans. This “defect” may be relevant for some purposes, but not for whether we treat humans exclusively as resources. We do not treat as things those humans who lack characteristics beyond sentience simply out of some sense of charity. We realize that to do so would violate the principle of equal consideration b y using an arbitrary reason to deny similar treatment to similar interests in not being treated exclusively as a means to the ends of others. “The question is not, Can they reason? nor, Can they talk? but, Can they suffer?”

In sum, there is no characteristic that serves to distinguish humans from all other animals for purposes of denying to animals the one right that we extend to all humans. Whatever attribute we may think makes all humans special and thereby deserving the right not to be the property of others is shared by nonhumans. More important, even if there are uniquely human characteristics, some humans will not possess those characteristics, but we would never think of using such humans as resources. In the end, the only difference between humans and animals is species, and species is not a justification for treating animals as property any more than race is a justification for human slavery.





Download 1.43 Mb.

Share with your friends:
1   ...   22   23   24   25   26   27   28   29   ...   133




The database is protected by copyright ©ininet.org 2024
send message

    Main page