Philosopher views



Download 5.81 Mb.
Page413/432
Date28.05.2018
Size5.81 Mb.
#50717
1   ...   409   410   411   412   413   414   415   416   ...   432

Utilitarianism Responses

I can will what is right, but I cannot do it. For I do not do the good I want, but the evil I do not want is what I do.”

-Paul the Apostle
Introduction
The promise of utilitarianism is, in a way, the promise of democracy. The political system that seeks to remove power from the hands of a few elites and give it to the “majority,” is part and parcel of the philosophical system that says that those consequences that are best for the majority are those consequences we ought to seek.
Given such a close connection between utilitarianism and democracy, one would think that supporting the latter almost necessarily means supporting the former. However, there is a difference between feeling that, politically, the will of the majority must be upheld and balanced with minority rights, and arguing that we ought to always act in accordance with a certain set of predictable consequences, and that those consequences must be calculated to give a certain number of people a certain amount of happiness.
The problem does not stem from any belief that people ought not be happy, or that the will of the majority ought not be respected. The problem I will outline in this essay stems from two basic tenants of utilitarian thought: (1) the idea that consequences can be predicted with sufficient accuracy to be a guide for ethical action; and (2) the idea that there is a general consensus of what counts as “utility-happiness” for a majority of people.
In this essay I will first outline the general principles of utilitarianism. Then I will make three basic arguments, which undermine the strength of that philosophy: First, consequences are too unpredictable to make them the center of moral agency. Second, measuring the desirability of consequences rests on an arbitrary and capricious notion of “welfare” or “happiness” which raises insolvable problems. Third, differences in value systems, especially according to class, render a general consensus of happiness impossible.
Although this essay is critical of utilitarianism as an absolute philosophy, I will conclude with the caveat that there are still some cases in which it is appropriate to adhere to utility, and consequences, as predictors of good behavior. My argument is simply that utilitarianism cannot be the center of our criteria for measuring the moral desirability of action. This does not mean that there aren’t some cases in which the philosophy can work, perhaps in tandem with other ethical criteria.

The philosophy of utility

In its simplest manifestation, utilitarianism holds that agents ought to act in a way that will maximize utility, and more specifically, maximize the good of as many people as possible. That act is right which produces the best consequences for the greatest number of people.


There are at least two interesting things from the outset about a philosophy of utility-maximization. The first is that utilitarianism seems to assume that singular moral agents make choices involving other agents, choices that produce strings of consequences felt by others. The second important characteristic of utilitarianism is that it assumes there is a measurable level of “happiness” or utility, measurable at least in the sense that it lends itself to some kind of assessment when the agent is making the choice in question. Both of these assumptions will be questioned later in this essay, but for now it is important to distinguish a little more about utilitarianism itself.
Because the basic form of utilitarianism begs the question of whether we are speaking of individual actions, or sets of actions expressed in general rules, philosophers have tried to separate utilitarianism into two different manifestations. They are:
1. Act Utilitarianism: "What effect will my doing this act in this situation have on the general balance of good over evil?"
2. Rule Utilitarianism: "What general rule when followed by all in situations like this would produce the greatest happiness for the greatest number?" (http://saul.snu.edu/syllabi/philosop/PHIL3013/301318.htm)
Because rule utilitarianism seems to be a more reasonable way to “make ethics,” most utilitarians today are rule-utilitarians, although rule-utilitarianism, it should be noted, also seems to encompass act utilitarianism at the level of individual choices. However, philosopher J. J. C. Smart argues that rule-utilitarianism ultimately collapses into act-utilitarianism:
“Suppose that an exception to rule R produces the best possible consequences. Then this is evidence that rule R should be modified so as to allow this exception. Thus we get a new rule for the form ‘do R except in circumstances of the sort C.’ That is, whatever would lead the act-utilitarian to break a rule would lead the Kantian utilitarian to modify the rule. Thus an adequate rule-utilitarianism would be extensionally equivalent to act-utilitarianism” (J. J. C. Smart, UTILITARIANISM FOR AND AGAINST, 1973, pp. 10-11).
So utilitarianism, whether in the form of general rules or individual acts, says agents should make choices based on predicted consequences, to maximize the good, for as many people as possible. Each of the components of this philosophy are questionable, and the following sections in the essay address each in turn.

The problem of unpredictability of consequences

The first of my objections is that utilitarianism assumes we can predict consequences. My argument is that we cannot. An example will illustrate this point:


Suppose I am walking along the waterfront and I see a child struggling in the water. Concerned that the child will drown, and knowing I am a good swimmer, my rule-utilitarian maxim kicks in: “I ought to act to save that child. It will result in good for the child, and (because I like to help people) good for me as well.” I have calculated the probable consequences of my action, and finding that the consequences will be desirable, I jump in the water. Swimming towards the struggling child, I prepare to save the child. Just then, the undertow strengthens. It sucks us both under. We both drown.
Now, other ethical formulas would hold that I did the right thing, even though the consequences were not desirable, and were not what I had planned. Utilitarianism, however, would force a retroactive condemnation of my action, because the consequences that finally resulted were actually worse than if I had done nothing, if I had just continued walking along the waterfront. For if I had kept walking, only one person would have drowned, but because I jumped in the water (and because of the undertow), two people drowned.
What is going on here? To begin with, utilitarianism cannot account for my intent alone. Unlike Kant’s categorical imperative, utilitarianism measures the morality of one’s actions based on the consequences. Thus, my intent to save the child is irrelevant. Regardless of any other consideration, this alone seems to render utilitarianism an incomplete moral philosophy. Surely I ought to receive my due “moral credit” simply for attempting to save the child, even if I fail.
But more importantly, utilitarianism seems to assume a universe full of predictable consequences. It seems to assume that if a moral agent acts upon the prediction of consequences, those consequences will behave as predicted. But the universe doesn’t work this way. Instead, the universe is “complex.” Actions result in more unpredictable than predictable consequences.
It is not a matter of human beings simply lacking the intellect to predict consequences. Rather, as philosophers of complexity point out, the very nature of actions and consequences is unpredictable. This unpredictability makes it impossible to assign responsibility to specific agents for specific consequences. Danilo Zolo explains some of the manifestations of reality’s complex nature in this way: Complexity “refers to the cognitive situation in which agents, whether they are individuals or social groups, find themselves. The relations which agents construct and project on their environment in their attempts at self-orientation—i.e. at arrangement, prediction, planning, manipulation—will be more or less complex according to circumstances.”
Similarly, as the situation becomes more complex, more laden with interdependent variables (as are almost all political situations), “the more interdependent the variables become. Variations in the value of one variable inevitably act on other variables (and so too they on it), making the task of cognition (and operation) more difficult…Once a certain threshold of complexity is crossed, the very quality changes of the calculations needed to predict the effects of the recursive relations which interconnect the environmental factors. Even analysis of individual phenomena becomes less certain, given that their basic condition—and developments from that condition—can scarcely be separated from the nexus of non-linear connections” (Danilo Zolo, Democracy and Complexity, 1992, pp. 6-7).
The drowning child example, and Zolo’s observations about complexity, suggest that utilitarianism can never really be a philosophy which offers any guidance for ethical actions, since those actions are to be measured by something that can never be measured: actions’ consequences.



Download 5.81 Mb.

Share with your friends:
1   ...   409   410   411   412   413   414   415   416   ...   432




The database is protected by copyright ©ininet.org 2024
send message

    Main page