Philosopher views



Download 5.81 Mb.
Page7/432
Date28.05.2018
Size5.81 Mb.
#50717
1   2   3   4   5   6   7   8   9   10   ...   432

BIBLIOGRAPHY



Adler, Mortimer J., "THE HUMAN EQUATION IN DIALECTIC,"Psyche 28 (April 1927), 68-82.
---,"SPENGLER, THE SPENGLERITES, AND SPENGLERISM," Psyche 29 (July 1927), 73-84.
---, DIALECTIC. New York: Harcourt, Brace and Company, 1927.

---, ART AND PRUDENCE: A STUDY IN PRACTICAL PHILOSOPHY. New York: Longmans, Green and Co., 1937.

---, WHAT MAN HAS MADE OF MAN: A STUDY OF THE CONSEQUENCES OF PLATONISM AND POSITIVISM IN PSYCHOLODY. Psychology. New York: Longmans, Green and Co., 1937.

---, “PARTIES AND THE COMON GOOD" The Review of Politics 1 (January 1939) 51-83.
---, “THE CRISIS IN CONTEMPORARY EDUCATION" The Social Frontier (February 1939), 140-145
---, RELIGON AND THEOLOGY. Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, 1961.
---, ETHICS, THE STUDY OF MORAL VALUES. Chicago: Encyclopedia Britannica, 1962.
---, THE CONDITIONS OF PHILOSOPHY; ITS CHECKERED PAST, ITS PRESENT DISORDER, AND ITS FUTURE PROMISE. New York: Atheneum, 1965.
---, FREEDOM: A STUDY OF THE DEVELOPMENT OF THE CONCEPT IN THE ENGLISH AND AMERICAN TRADITIONS OF PHILOSOPHY. Albany, N.Y.: Magi Books, 1968.
---, THE TIME OF OUR LIVES; THE ETHICS OF COMMON SENSE. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1970.
---, THE IDEA OF FREEDOM. Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press, 1973.
---, THE AMERICAN TESTAMENT. New York: Praeger, 1975.
---, PHILOSOPHER AT LARGE: AN INTELECTUAL BIOGRAPHY. New York: Macmillan, 1977.
---, REFORMING EDUCATIONS: THE SCHOOLING OF A PEOPLE AND THIER EDUCATION BEYOND SCHOOLING. Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1977.

---, THE PAIDEIA PROPOSAL: AN EDUCATIONAL MANIFESTO. New York: Macmillan, 1982.
---, A VISION OF THE FUTURE: TWELVE IDEAS FOR A BETTER LIFE AND A BETTER SOCIETY. New York: Macmillan, 1984
---, TEN PHILOSOPHICAL MISTAKES. New York: Collier Books, 1987.
---, REFORMING EDUCATION: THE OPENING OF THE AMERICAN MIND. New York: Macmillan, 1989
---, INTELLECT: MIND OVER MATTER. New York: Macmillan. 1990.
---, HAVES WITHOUT HAVE-NOTS: ESSAYS FOR THE 21ST CENTURY ON DEMOCRACY AND SOCIALISM. New York: Macmillan, 1991.
---, DESIRES,RIGHT & WRONG: THE ETHICS OF ENOUGH. New York: Macmillan, 1991.
---, THE DIFFERENCE OF MAN AND THE DIFFERENCE IT MAKES. New York: Fordham University Press, 1993.
---, THE ANGELS AND US. New York: Collier Books, 1993
---, THE FOUR DIMENSIONS OF PHILOSOPHY: METAPHYSICAL, MORAL, OBJECTIVE, CATEGORICAL. New York: Macmillan Pub. Co, 1993.
---, ARISTOTLE FOR EVERYBODY: DIFFICULT THOUGH MADE EASY. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1997.
---, HOW TO SPEAK, HOW TO LISTEN. New York: Simon & Schuster, 1997.

PHILOSOPHICAL "TRUTH'S" DON'T EXIST

1. THE PURSUIT OF EPISTEMIC KNOWLEDGE IS ILLUSORY

Mortimer Adler, philosopher, THE CONDITIONS OF PHILSOPHY, 1965, p. 30.

Episteme represents an illusory ideal that has bemused man’s understanding of his efforts and his achievements in the pursuit of knowledge. It has led philosophers to misconceive philosophy and to make unsupportable claims for their theories or conclusions. In that branch of philosophy which is called epistemology (especially in the form that it takes in contemporary Anglo-American thought), the abandonment of episteme would eliminate three problems with which it obsessed—the problem of our knowledge of material objects, of other minds, and of the past. These are baffling, perhaps insoluble, problems only when they claim is made that we can have knowledge of material objects, other minds, and the past—knowledge which has the certitude and finality of doxa for episteme, and the problems cease to be problems, or at least to be baffling. Abandoning episteme as an illusory ideal would not only shrink epistemology to its proper size, but it would also starve, if not silence, the skeptic who feeds on the claim to achieve episteme in any department of human inquiry.
2. A MODERATE INTERPREATION OF KNOWLEDGE AS OPINION IS MORE ACCURATE

Mortimer Adler, philosopher, THE CONDITIONS OF PHILSOPHY, 1965, p. 28.

In what sense of knowledge, then, are history, science, mathematics, and philosophy branches of knowledge? If episteme sets too high a standard, what is the moderate or weaker sense of the word “knowledge” in which it is applicable—and equally applicable—to the disciplines just mentioned?

The properties of knowledge in this moderate sense are that it consists of propositions which are (1) testable by reference to evidence, (2) subject to rational criticism, and either (3) corrigible and rectifiable or (4) falsifiable. The Greeks had another word which I propose to use for “knowledge” in this sense. That word is doxa, and it is usually rendered in English by the word “opinion.” As the properties enumerated above indicate, what is being referred to is responsible, reliable, well-founded, reasonable opinion. When the English word “opinion” is used to signify the opposite of knowledge, what is being referred to usually lacks these very properties. It is irresponsible, unreliable, unfounded, unreasonable; it is mere opinion, sheer opinion, irrational prejudice.


3. PHILSOPHY IS ONLY A BRANCH OF KNOWLEDGE

Mortimer Adler, philosopher, THE CONDITIONS OF PHILSOPHY, 1965, p.21-24

To be intellectually respectable, as history and science are generally recognized to be, philosophy must be a branch of knowledge. It must be a mode of inquiry that aims at, and results in, the acquisition of knowledge which is characteristically different from the knowledge that is aimed at and achieved by historical scholarship and scientific research. There is a sense of the word “knowledge” which sets too high a standard of achievement for it to be applicable to either historical scholarship or scientific research. At times in the past, it was thought that mathematics could measure up to this high standard. At times, philosophy also was thought to be knowledge in this high or strong sense. But in the centuries which have seen the greatest development of scientific research and historical scholarship, it has seldom, if ever, been thought that either scientific or historical knowledge was knowledge in this sense.

All that is required by the first condition is that philosophy should aim at and acquire knowledge in the same sense that science and history do, not in a loftier sense of that term.

The attributes of [epistemic] knowledge in the high or strong sense are: (1) certitude beyond the challenge of skeptical doubts, (2) finality beyond the possibility of revision in the course of time. Such knowledge consists entirely of (3) necessary truths, which have either the status of (4) self-evident principles, that is, axioms, or of (5) conclusions rigorously demonstrated therefrom.



Download 5.81 Mb.

Share with your friends:
1   2   3   4   5   6   7   8   9   10   ...   432




The database is protected by copyright ©ininet.org 2024
send message

    Main page