Philosophical Naturalism David Papineau For Katy



Download 0.69 Mb.
Page18/25
Date28.05.2018
Size0.69 Mb.
#51224
1   ...   14   15   16   17   18   19   20   21   ...   25

6.5  Postulationism


The difficulty raised for mathe matical anti-realism in the last section was in effect that mathematical practice seems just to assume the axioms from which it starts proofs, and does nothing to establish those axioms.  But perhaps anti-realists could respond that the peculiarity o f mathematics is precisely that its basic assumptions don't need any further proof, on the grounds that the requisite mathematical objects will automatically be available to satisfy any consistent set of mathematical assumptions.

   I shall call this attitude towards mathematics "postulationism", since it implies that no further justification is needed for a mathematical theory than the consistency of its postulates.  At first sight postulationism might seem to make mathematical existen ce unacceptably dependent on human activity, with mathematical objects somehow springing into existence as mathematicians formulate assumptions.  But we needn't understand the postulationist theory in such a strongly anthropocentric way.  Rather the idea could be that there is a timeless Platonist realm in which there are abstract objects satisfying any possible set of consistent mathematcial axioms, whether or not anybody has yet thought of those axioms.4

   This would of course mean that there are an awful lot of mathematical objects -- as well the familar objects of standard mathematics, there will also be such non-standard objects as all the different kinds of numbers modulo n, and all the shapes in all possible geom etries, and all the operators in all possible vector spaces, and indeed all kinds of things that have never been thought of and never will be.  But perhaps there's nothing wrong with that.  Large universes are scarcely alien to mathematics.

   A more substantial objection to postulationism might be that mathematicians themselves make a distinction between those branches of mathematics whose existence claims they take seriously and those whose they don't.  The complaint here wo uld in a sense be the mirror image of the claim levelled against "if-thenism".  Where "if-thenism" says that all mathematics is meant hypothetically, "postulationism" seems to imply that all mathematics can be asserted unconditionally.  But this then means that "postulationism" is open to a mirror image of the objection made to "if-thenism":  since there are branches of mathematics in which mathematicians do restrict themselves to hypothetical attitudes, considering the axioms as assumption s whose consequences are worth exploring, rather than as claims to be believed, it is wrong to read all mathematics as unconditionally assertible.

   However, I think that postulationism has a reasonable answer to this complaint.  For t here is a natural way for postulationism to distinguish between those branches of  mathematics which it appropriate to understand hypothetically and those which which it appropriate to understand unconditionally, a way which seems to line up accurate ly with the way practising mathematicians make this distinction.  Postulationists can appeal to the distinction between sets of axioms which are categorical, in the technical sense of determining a unique model, up to isomorphism, and those which are not so categorical.  The axioms of group theory, for instance, are not categorical, in that quite disparate sets of objects, of different cardinalities, can form groups.  Peano's postulates, by contrast, are categorical (in second-order logic), in that any set of objects and relations which satisfy them can be placed in a structure-preserving one-to-one correspondence.  So the natural move for postulationism is to argue that mathematical objects are available to satisfy every consistent an d categorical set of axioms;  non-categorical axiom sets, by contrast, do not guarantee the existence of any mathematical objects, and so should be read hypothetically, as saying merely that if there are any objects which . . ., then . . .

    This suggestion accords well with actual mathematical practice.  Mathematicians certainly seem to be committed, as I have already observed, to the numbers 0, 1, and all their successors, as existing objects.  By contrast, it makes little mathematical sense to talk about the identity element mentioned in the axioms of group theory.  Yet, even within group theory, once we add enough special assumptions to the general axioms of group theory to give us categoricity, then, in line with th e current suggestion, we do find mathematicians talking unconditionally about the simple group of order 68, the elliptic modular group, and so on, as if these special groups, at least, were as real as the number one.

   So postulationism can answer the charge that it makes all mathematics unconditionally assertible. It simply restrict its ontological commitment to those abstract objects required to satisfy categorical mathematical theories.  This then implies, in accord with existing ma thematical practice, that only such categorical theories should be unconditionally asserted, and that non-categorical theories should merely be embraced hypothetically.

   There is, however, another rather more telling objection to postulati onism.  According to postulationism, as now understood, all objects that can consistently and categorically be postulated thereby exist.  But how then does postulationism differ from a fictionalist attitude to mathematical objects?  If ever ything that can consistently and categorically be thought to exist thereby does exist, then won't Sherlock Holmes exist, and Santa Claus, and the Wicked Witch of the North?5  Perhaps it is natural to slip into unreflective acceptance of ca tegorical truths about numbers and sets and simple groups.  But if all this really amounts to is accepting what follows from assumptions agreed by mathematicians, why is it any different from accepting what follows from our agreed assumptions about S anta Claus?

   The postulationist might object that the comparison is not fair.  If we take claims about Sherlock Holmes and Santa Claus literally, then these claims are about people who inhabit the same spatiotemporal world as we do.&n bsp; And on this literal reading these claims can be shown to be false.  Maybe the stories are internally consistent, but they aren't consistent with the totality of our beliefs about the world.  Which is why we don't in fact accept these claims literally, and why we don't accord Shylock and Santa Claus real existence, but only fictional "existence", that is, non-existence.  By contrast, claims about mathematical objects aren't about spatiotemporal objects.  So nothing forces us to reg ard them as literally false, nor to regard the objects they mention as mere fictions.

   But I don't think that this is good enough.  It still seems to me that the postulationist story as told so far gives us no reason to view mathemati cal existence as anything more than fictional non-existence.  Maybe the definite reasons which force us to adopt fictional attitudes to explicit fictions don't carry over to the mathematical case.  But, even so, the postulationist hasn't told us anything more about what's involved in mathematical existence, other than that a consistent and categorical story can be told about the objects in question.  Such a story guarantees fictional "existence".  But if mathematical existence is to am ount to more than the non-existence of fictional "existence", then there must be something more at issue than an internally consistent story, for abstract objects just as for concrete ones.


 
 


Download 0.69 Mb.

Share with your friends:
1   ...   14   15   16   17   18   19   20   21   ...   25




The database is protected by copyright ©ininet.org 2024
send message

    Main page