Philosophical Naturalism David Papineau For Katy


  Fictionalism and Modality



Download 0.69 Mb.
Page25/25
Date28.05.2018
Size0.69 Mb.
#51224
1   ...   17   18   19   20   21   22   23   24   25

6.15  Fictionalism and Modality


In this final secti on I want to say a bit more about modality, and in particular about the use that fictionalism makes of this notion.

   Note first that fictionalism needs to make assumptions about logical consequence, in at least two places.  First, and most obviously, the claim that mathematics is dispensable in science rests on the premise that it is conservative with respect to nominalist truths -- that is, that no nominalist conclusions follow logically from nominalist-premises-plus-mathematics that don't follow from nominalist premises alone.

   Second, fictionalists need the notion of logical consequence to identify what they mean by "mathematics" in the first place.  For the kind of mathematics that fictionalists think is dispe nsable, though nevertheless useful as a fiction, isn't just any old set of claims formulated in mathematical vocabulary (for that wouldn't be conservative, or useful), but rather standard, or accepted, or good mathematics.  So fictionalists owe us so me account of what standard mathematics is, some account of what exactly it is that they are recommending we accept as a fiction.  And the obvious account is that standard mathematics consists of all the claims that follow logically from standard mat hematical assumptions.

   I shall now show that we fictionalists need to understand such claims about logical consequence in modal terms:  that is, we need to understand the claim that B follows logically from {A} as equivalent to it is not possible that {A} all be true and B false.

   This may not be immediately obvious.  Why can't the fictionalist avoid modality by simply appealing to the standard characterizations of logical consequence in metalogic?  For exam ple, why not explain consequence semantically, saying B is a logical consequence of {A} if and only if B is true in all models in which all members of {A} are true?  Alternatively, why not offer a syntactic analysis, saying that B is a logical conseq uence of {A} if and only if B can be proved from {A} using a specified set of rules of inference?

   The characterizations are unquestionably of great mathematical significance.  However, there are reasons why we fictionalists cannot re st with either of them as a philosophical account of logical consequence.  Let me take the semantic characterization first.  The obvious problem is that models are themselves abstract mathematical objects, and therefore, given the overall argume nt of this chapter, not something we can have beliefs about.23   (In the end, of course, we should be able to regard such claims about models, along with other mathematical claims, as useful parts of the mathematical fiction.  Bu t at this stage we still face the task of explaining what exactly the mathematical fiction comprises.)

   The alternative metalogical characterization of logical consequence, in terms of syntax, specifies a set of rules of inference for movi ng between sentences with certain syntactic forms.  The normal objection to fictionalists accepting this characterization is that rules of inferences and syntactic forms are themselves abstract objects, and so inadmissible from our fictionalist persp ective.24   But this is less than compelling;  there seems plenty of room to view such syntactic entities as features of certain physical systems, namely, languages.  However, there are worse problems facing a fictionalist w ho appeals to the syntactic explanation of logical consequence.  These arise from the fact that nothing stronger than first-order logic can be completely characterized in syntactic terms.  So, for a start, there is a problem about the fictionali st delineation of standard mathematics as whatever follows from the standard axioms.  If "follows from" simply means whatever follows by first-order logic, then Godel's theorem tells us that there will be mathematical truths which do not so follow fr om the standard axioms, contrary to the fictionalist's delineation of standard mathematics.

   A related Godelian difficulty faces the fictionalist's claim that standard mathematics is conservative with respect to bodies of nominalist assert ions.  For consider, as the relevant body of nominalist assertions, the claim that there exists a geometrical point, and another point, and then another as far away again in the same direction, . . .  By such means we can construct a nominalist version of Peano's axioms, which refers to geometrical points instead of the natural numbers.  But now there will be a "nominalized version" of a Godel sentence which does not follow logically from these axioms, if "follow from" means by first-order logic.  However, this nominalized Godel sentence will follow in first-order logic if we are allowed to add pure arithmetic plus appropriate bridge principles to the nominalist Peano axioms, since pure arithmetic will include the pure version of this Godel sentence.  The upshot is that pure mathematics, and in particular pure arithmetic, is not conservative with respect to bodies of nominalist assertions, if by "conservative" we mean that the addition of mathematics to nominalist assumptions gene rates no new conclusions within first-order logic.25

   So a fictionalist cannot happily rest either with the model-theoretic or with the syntactic characterization of logical consequence.  Suppose, however, that we take the modal notions of necessity and possibility as primitive, and define consequence in modal terms in the way suggested above, as the impossibility of the premises being true and the conclusion being false.  This then evades the difficulties facing the s tandard semantic and syntactic characterizations.  There is no obvious commitment to abstract objects like models in this definition.  And since there is no reason to regard the consequence relation thus defined as restricted to first-order cons equence, the Godelian difficulties need no longer apply.

   If the arguments of the last few sections are right, it follows that the appropriate attitude to claims of logical consequence will not be belief, but rather a non-doxastic attitude of unqualified commitment to the corresponding forms of argument.  Of course, there is nothing to stop us believing that, whenever the premises of such arguments are true, then the conclusions will be true too, that is, that such arguments are relia ble.  But the further thought, that these arguments are necessarily reliable, will not itself be a belief.26

   As I observed in passing earlier, a non-doxastic view of necessity raises the question of whether our normal crit eria for making judgements of necessity provide appropriate grounds for the relevant non-doxastic attitude.  In the present context, where we are using necessity to explain logical consequence, there are also a number of further technical issues, whi ch I cannot pursue here, about whether these criteria are adequate to the mathematical structure of logical consequence.27   However let me make just one point.  A standard soundness proof for some form of argument, such as is gi ven by the truth table for modus ponens, say, provides an obvious vindication of an unqualified commitment to the reliability of that form of argument.  Such a proof can simply be thought of as arguing in the alternative, for all the possible alterna tive arrangements of semantic values for non-logical expressions which would make the premises true, that the conclusion would be true too.28   So such a soundness proof provides an immediate basis for belief in the reliability of the form of argument in question.  And since the proof hinges on no assumptions save those about the meaning of logical expressions, it also provides obvious grounds for an unqualified commitment to that form of argument.
 

1. There is a pr oblem of terminology here.  In some circles, especially American ones, philosophers like Bas van Fraassen are called "anti-realists", not because they hold that there is no substantial possibility of erroroneous belief, but, on the contrary, because they fear that this possibility is actual (cf Van Fraassen, 1980).  However, in my terminology, and in contemporary British usage, Van Fraassen is not an anti-realist, but rather a pessimistic realist, that is, a sceptic.  To get things straight , we need to distinguish three positions:  anti-realism, in the British sense, which denies the conceptual possibility of error;  optimistic realism, which admits the conceptual possibility of error, but disputes its actuality;  and pessimi stic realism, or scepticism, which fears that error is not only possible but actual.  In what follows, unqualified uses of the terms "anti-realism", "realism", and "scepticism" should be understood to stand for these three positions respectively.&nbs p; That is, I shall reserve the term "anti-realism" for philosophers who uphold beliefs on the grounds they can't be false;  philosophers who reject beliefs because they fear they are false will be called "sceptics".

2. For more on the different varieties of anti-realism and their problems, see Papineau (1987, ch 1).
 

 3. I would make the same point about contemporary "structuralist" or "modal-structuralist" views, which read mathematics as saying only that there exist, or poss ibly exist, some objects satisfying the axioms, and that therefore the theorems are true of those objects, or of those possible objects, whatever they might be.  (Cf Lewis, 199x, pp xx-xx; Hellman 1989, 1990.)  Whatever other virtues these views may have (but cf footnote 22 below), they are unquestionably revisionary proposals.  The same goes for Michael Resnik's (1981, 1982) more platonist species of structuralism;  this also faces extra problems, because of its reification of "struct ures" (cf Chihara, 1990, ch 7).

4  I have found this position defended more often in conversation than in writing.

5. Are these stories categorical?  The plethora of Santa Clauses who appear around Christmas might make us wonder.  B ut such stories can easily be made categorical, by including the explicit provisos that there is only one genuine Santa Claus, only one genuine Sherlock Holmes, and so on.

6. It is true that (6) is a truth of second-order logic, and some philosophersw ill feel that this commits (6) to sets, thus reintroducing the epistemological difficulties of abstract objects.  But this is by no means uncontentious:  in a series of recent papers George Boolos (1975, 1984, 1985) has defended higher-order qua ntification against the charge of implicit reference to sets.  See also Wright (1983) pp 132-3.

7. For an interesting recent version of this generally Russellian approach, see Hodes (1984).  Cf also Lear (1982).  It is worth distinguish ing this "reductionist" approach from the "if-thenism" mentioned in section 2.  Both approaches claim that there is nothing more to mathematical knowledge than logical knowledge.  But "if-thenism" does so by arguing that mathematical knowledge i s always knowledge that if such-and-such axioms hold, then certain theorems follow.  The reductionist approach, by contrast, needs to show that the axioms (and so the theorems) are themselves logical truths.

8. Hodes (1984) holds that the constru ction "the number of . . ." is systematically ambiguous, but gets disambiguated when the gap is filled in.  This is reasonably plausible.  What is not so plausible is the claim that "2" is ambiguous in "2 + 3 = 5".

9. Cf Hodes op cit p 144-6 ; Lear op cit p 188-91.

10. Note however that reductionism, as I have characterized it, is technically more demanding than Field's fictionalism:  the reductionist needs to find, for every mathematical claim, some (family of) quantificational surr ogate(s) which yields the same inferential power;  while Field is only committed to holding that all inferences underpinned by mathematical claims can be made by logic alone, and not to a case-by-case pairing of mathematical claims with quantificatio nal equivalents.

11. It is perhaps unfair to accuse Hodes (op cit) of wanting to have it both ways, since he explicitly embraces a kind of fictionalism (p 146), and to that extent explicitly abandons his reductionist ambitions.  Lear (op cit), on the other hand, does seem to want to have it both ways.  He shows how the possibility of holding reduced beliefs which do not involve abstract objects makes it both harmless but useful to work with mathematical propositions that do.  But he the n claims that this legitimates belief in the mathematical propositions.

12. This provides a route to knowledge of arithmetic.  But what about the rest of mathematics?  Well, it is arguable that the rest of mathematics is reducible to set the ory.  Moreover, there is a plausible set-theoretical analogue to N=, namely, the conceptual equivalence of:

(9)   (x)(Fx <-> Gx), and

(10)   The set of Fs = the set of Gs.

But of course, as it stands, this is too st rong:  without some restrictions on what can be substituted for F and G, Russell's paradox will follow.  Still, there remain weaker eqivalences which are both pre-theoretically plausible and powerful enough to yield set theory.  I shall not pursue this line of thought, however, since the criticisms I am about to make of Wright's account of arithmetic will carry over to any analogous account of set theory.

13. For details of this line of argument, see Hale (1987, ch 2).

14. Of course , theoretical claims aren't conservative with respect to observational claims in the strong sense that extra theoretical premises never augment the consequences of any set of observational premises.  But Craig's theorem does show that adding the clai ms of some theory to the observational consequences of that theory does not augment observational consequences.  So to that extent theories are dispensable for drawing observational conclusions.

15. In what follows "necessary" should be understoo d in the narrow sense of logically necessary.  I take it that other kinds of necessity (physical, conceptual, legal, and so on) can be defined in terms of logically necessity (as necesary consequences of physical laws, conceptual laws, legal laws, an d so on).  In the case of physical necessity, there is of course the extra problem of distinguishing physical laws from accidentally true generalizations.  In my (1986a) I advocated a fictionalist view of this distinction.  I now think this was a mistake.  My current view is that we can distinguish physical laws as consquences of those true generalizations which have sufficient robustness to qualify as causal.  But that is another story.

16. As, for example, in Ayer (1936, ch 6).

17. Cf McFetridge (1990, essay VIII).

18. Simon Blackburn (1984, 1986) has coined the term "quasi-realism" to emphasize the structural affinities between normal discourse and moral and modal discourse.  As it happens, Blackburn also upholds the "projectivist" view that moral and modal judgements express attitudes other than belief.  The question I am currently asking (though Blackburn does not) is why his "quasi-realism" doesn't undermine his "projectivism".   Fo r this point, see Wright (1987).  See also Hale (1986) for further discussion of Blackburn's position.

19. So I agree with Van Fraassen, and disagree with Horwich, that it is psychologically possible to "think with" a theory, and yet not believei t.  But I certainly don't agree with Van Fraassen's further sceptical claim that this is the appropriate attitude to all scientific theories.  Cf my remarks about the epistemology of theory-choice in 6.10 above.

20. Why exactly should belief be subject to epistemological requirements not imposed on other attitudes?  A short answer is that belief is that attitude which is supposed to represent how things are, as opposed to how they are taken to be.  This is why beliefs require evide nce, and cannot be made true just by being part of some established intellectual practice.

21. Note that the intended reference to mathematical objects is the reason why fictionalism is the appropriate non-doxastic attitude in mathematics.  I hav e already explained why this non-doxastic attitude will involve a sceptical element: it requires us to reject the mathematical beliefs I conjecture most people to hold.  But such a sceptical attitude needn't be fictionalist.  To see this, imagin e a community who did have moral beliefs whose content derived from a non-object-introducing moral operator of the kind mentioned above.  Then, I say, we ought to reject those beliefs in favour of a non-doxastic moral attitude.  This attitude wo uld thus be sceptical about those people's moral beliefs.  But it wouldn't be fictionalist, for lack of any moral objects to populate the fiction.  In mathematics, by contrast, we have intended mathematical objects to provide our fiction.
&n bsp;
22. Even if such non-objectual views are wrong about the meaning of mathematical claims, might they not be defended as revisionary proposals?  This is possible, but there is an obvious respect in which the revision proposed by fictionalism i s preferable.  Fictionalism only requires a revision in attitude, where these alternatives require a revision in content.  Apart from this, the explanations of the applicability of mathematics offered by if-thenism and reductionism are technical ly more demanding than that offered by fictionalism.  The extra requirements facing reductionism are those noted in footnote 10 above.  The problem facing if-thenism is that it can only account for the applicability of mathematical theories to s ets of natural objects which provide models of those theories;  yet we often apply mathematical theories to setsc of natural objects which are too sparse to yield such models.

23. For other objections to the semantic characterization of logical c onsequences, which apply even if you don't mind abstract objects, see Field (19xx) and McGee (1991).

24. Cf Putnam, 1971, ch 2; Field, 1984, p 514.

25. This Godelian argument is due to Shapiro (1983).  At first sight Shapiro's argument might seem inconsistent with the proof of the conservativeness of mathematics given by Field in Science Without Numbers.  However, what Field proves is that mathematics is conservative with respect to first-order nominalized theories.  The kind of geo metrical theory needed to mimic Peano's postulates, by contrast, requires more than first-order quantification, which is why it escapes Field's proof.  This leaves Field with a problem, however, since he himself requires just this kind of nonfirstord erizable geometrical theory to nominalize physics.  (Cf Chihara 1990, ch 8 and Appendix.)

26. This answers a point raised by Hale (1987, p 120).

27. But see Field (19xx) for an investigation of a primitively modal interpretation of logical consequence.  I should make it clear that Field does not himself advocate a non-doxastic approach.  But it seems to me that many of his points could be adopted by someone who does.



28. As a fictionalist, I don't want to read such so undness proofs as showing that the conclusion is true in all models in which the premises are true.  My idea is rather that they assume that (in actuality) either X or Y or . . ., and conclude that (in actuality) either the premises are false or the conclusion true.

Download 0.69 Mb.

Share with your friends:
1   ...   17   18   19   20   21   22   23   24   25




The database is protected by copyright ©ininet.org 2024
send message

    Main page