Planet Debate 2011 September/October l-d release Animal Rights


Viewing Animals as Property Negatively Impacts How People Treat Each Other



Download 1.43 Mb.
Page10/133
Date16.08.2017
Size1.43 Mb.
#33284
1   ...   6   7   8   9   10   11   12   13   ...   133

Viewing Animals as Property Negatively Impacts How People Treat Each Other



UNIVERSALIZING ALL NONHUMAN ANIMALS AS “THINGS” OR “PROPERTY” WILL FRAME HOW WE VIEW OTHER HUMANS

Mark Rowlands, Professor of Moral Philosophy, University of Hertfordshire, 2002, Animals Like Us, p. 205-6



Heidegger, with whom we began this chapter, talked of the view of nature as a resource as stemming from a conceptualization of the world he called a gestell, which can be translated “framework” or “matrix.” The danger of the gestell, or one of its dangers, is its tendency to universality. If we view nature, and all things in it, as simply resources, then it is inevitable we eventually acquire the same view of human beings. But viewing human beings as resources has two facets. Obviously, one thing it means is that you will view other human beings as resources. Less obviously, you are yourself a human being, and you will come to think of yourself as a resource also.

**Should Recognize Rights for Animals**

Moral Framework Should be Extended to Animals


SHOULD EXTEND OUR ETHICAL AND MORAL FRAMEWORKS FOR TREATING PEOPLE APPROPRIATELY MODIFIED TO NON-HUMAN ANIMALS

Bernard E. Rollin, Professor of Philosophy, Colorado State University, 1995, Farm Animal Welfare: social, bioethical, and research issues, p. 16

As we have seen, society has grown increasingly concerned about animal suffering even when the source of the suffering is not cruelty, most notably in the case of research and confinement agriculture, but also in such areas as trapping. Indeed, a 1985 case in New York State vividly pointed out the need for ethical evolution beyond cruelty. A group of attorneys brought suit against the branch of New York State government charged with administering public lands on the grounds that the agency’s permitting the use of steel-jawed traps on public lands entailed violation of the cruelty laws, since animals trapped were deprived of food, water, and medical care for injury. Although sympathetic to the moral point, the judge dismissed the case, reiterating that cruelty laws did not apply to “standard” practices such as trapping, which fulfill a legal human purpose – provision of furs and pest control. If the plaintiffs wished to ban steel-jawed traps, said the judge, they needed to go to the legislature, that is, change the social ethic, not the judiciary, which is bound b the ethic encoded in the anticruelty law.

Thus, society is faced with the need for new moral categories and laws that reflect those categories in order to deal with animal use in science and agriculture and to limit the animal suffering with which it is increasingly concerned. At the same time, society has gone through almost fifty years of extending its moral categories for humans to people who were morally ignored or invisible. As noted, new and viable ethics does not emerge ex nihilo. So a plausible and obvious move is for society to continue in its tendency and attempt to extend the moral machinery it has developed for dealing with people, appropriately modified, to animals. And this is precisely what has occurred. Society has taken elements of the moral categories it uses for assessing the treatment of people and is in the process of modifying these concepts to make them appropriate for dealing with new issues in the treatment of animals, especially their use in science and confinement agriculture.


SHOULD ADOPT AN ETHIC THAT RESPECTS THE INTERESTS OF NON-HUMAN ANIMALS DERIVED FROM THEIR NATURE AND INTERESTS – NOT EQUAL RIGHTS

Bernard E. Rollin, Professor of Philosophy, Colorado State University, 1995, Farm Animal Welfare: social, bioethical, and research issues, p. 17-8

It is necessary to stress here certain things that this ethic, in its mainstream version, is not and does not attempt to be. As a mainstream movement, it does not try to give human rights to animals. Since animals do not have the same natures and interests flowing from there natures as humans do, human rights do not fit animals. Animals do not have basic natures that demand speech, religion, or property; thus according them these rights would be absurd. On the other hand, animals have natures of their own (what I have, following Aristotle, called their telos) and interests that flow from these natures, and the thwarting of these interests matters to animals as much as the thwarting of speech matters to humans. The agenda is not, for mainstream society, making animals “equal” to people. It is rather preserving the commonsense insight that “fish gotta swim and birds gotta fly,” and suffer if they don’t.

Nor is this ethic, in the minds of mainstream society, an abolitionist one, dictating that animals cannot be used by humans. Rather, it is an attempt to constrain how they can be used, so as to limit their pain and suffering. In this regard, as a 1993 Beef Today article points out, the thrust for protection of animal nature is not at all radical; it is very conservative, asking for the same sort of husbandry that characterized the overwhelming majority of animal use during all of human history, save the last fifty or so years. It is not opposed to animal use, it is opposed to animal use that goes against the animals’ natures and tries to force square pegs into round holes, leading to friction and suffering. If animals are to be used for food and labor, they should, as they traditionally did, live lives that respect their natures. If animals are to be used to probe nature and cure disease for human benefit, they should not suffer in the process. Thus this new ethic is conservative, not radical, harking back to the animal use that necessitated and thus entailed respect for the animals’ natures. It is based on the insight that what we do to animals matters to them, just as what we do to humans matters to them, and that consequently we should respect that mattering in our treatment and use of humans. And since respect for animal nature is no longer automatic as it was in traditional agriculture, society is demanding that it be encoded in law.



Download 1.43 Mb.

Share with your friends:
1   ...   6   7   8   9   10   11   12   13   ...   133




The database is protected by copyright ©ininet.org 2024
send message

    Main page