Affirmative Evidence Packet



Download 0.65 Mb.
Page10/13
Date10.08.2017
Size0.65 Mb.
#30497
1   ...   5   6   7   8   9   10   11   12   13

Disadvantage Overview

Regardless of what disadvantage the negative runs in the debate, the following argument should help the affirmative frame the decision of the judge to emphasize the strength of the affirmative impact in contrast with the negative impact of the disadvantage. The overview seeks to compare the magnitude, risk and time-frame of the negative arguments with the magnitude, risk and time frame of the impacts the affirmative claims to solve.



Disadvantage Overview 1/2


The disadvantage is highly uncertain and cannot justify voting negative.
1. A number of arguments prove that the disadvantage impact is not unique and is inevitable

whether or not you vote Affirmative.
2. The disadvantage also does not link to the affirmative, further proving that the affirmative

does not increase the risk of the impact.
3. The affirmative also outweighs the negative two ways:

A. Obesity. Over 100,000 people die each year. Unless you vote for the plan, you

condemn one million people to die over the next ten years. The probability that

you will cause a nuclear war is obscenely small compared to the certain death as

a result of voting negative.

B. Social Justice. Current transportation is a form of apartheid, excluding

particular groups of society from full participation in society. Our continued

acceptance of this racist governance condemns tens of millions to a new form of

slavery that should outweigh the minimal risk of nuclear war.

Giroux 6 (Henry, the Global TV Network Chair Professorship at McMaster University in the English and Cultural Studies Department,

“Reading Hurricane Katrina: Race, Class, and the Biopolitics of Disposability,” College Literature, Vol. 33, No. 3)



With the social state in retreat and the rapacious dynamics of neoliberalism, unchecked by government regulations, the public and private policies of investing in the public good are dismissed as bad business, just as the notion of protecting people from the dire misfortunes of poverty, sickness, or the random blows of fate is viewed as an act of bad faith. Weakness is now a sin, punishable by social exclusion. This is especially true for those racial groups and immigrant populations who have always been at risk economically and politically. Increasingly, such groups have become part of an evergrowing army of the impoverished and disenfranchised—removed from the prospect of a decent job, productive education, adequate health care, acceptable child care services, and satisfactory shelter. As the state is transformed into the primary agent of terror and corporate concerns displace democratic values, dominant “power is measured by the speed with which responsibilities can be escaped” (Qtd. in Fearn 2006, 30).With its pathological disdain for social values and public life and its celebration of an unbridled individualism and acquisitiveness, the Bush administration does more than undermine the nature of social obligation and civic responsibility; it also sends a message to those populations who are poor and black—society neither wants, cares about, or needs you (Bauman 1999, 68-69). Katrina revealed with startling and disturbing clarity who these individuals are: African- Americans who occupy the poorest sections of New Orleans, those ghettoized frontier-zones created by racism coupled with economic inequality. Cut out of any long term goals and a decent vision of the future, these are the populations, as Zygmunt Bauman points out, who have been rendered redundant and disposable in the age of neoliberal global capitalism. Katrina reveals that we are living in dark times.The shadow of authoritarianism remains after the storm clouds and hurricane winds have passed, offering a glimpse of its wreckage and terror. The politics of a disaster that affected Louisiana, Alabama, and Mississippi is about more than government incompetence, militarization, socio-economic polarization, environmental disaster, and political scandal. Hurricane Katrina broke through the visual blackout of poverty and the pernicious ideology of color-blindness to reveal the government’s role in fostering the dire conditions of largely poor African-Americans, who were bearing the hardships incurred by the full wrath of the indifference and violence at work in the racist, neoliberal state. Global neoliberalism and its victims now occupy a space shaped by authoritarian politics, the terrors inflicted by a police state, and a logic of disposability that removes them from government social provisions and the discourse and privileges of citizenship. One of the most obvious lessons of Katrina—that race and racism still matter in America—is fully operational through a biopolitics in which “sovereignty resides in the power and capacity to dictate who may live and who may die” (Mbembe 11-12).Those poor minorities of color and class, unable to contribute to the prevailing consumerist ethic, are vanishing into the sinkhole of poverty in desolate and abandoned enclaves of decaying cities, neighborhoods, and rural spaces, or in America’s ever-expanding prison empire. Under the Bush regime, a biopolitics driven by the waste machine of what Zygmunt Bauman defines as “liquid modernity” registers a new and brutal racism as part of the emergence of a contemporary and savage authoritarianism.

Disadvantage Overview 2/2



4. Reject appeals to cold economic cost-benefit analysis – societal conditions are created by the decisionmaking processes we use in formulating policies – and utilitarian calculus eventually results in

ignoring groups most affected by racism
Wenz 1 (Peter S., Professor of Philosophy and Legal Studies at Sangamon State University and adjunct

Professor of Medical Humanities at Southern Illinois University School of Medicine, , Faces of

Environmental Racism: Confronting Issues of Global Justice (2nd ed.,), p. 63-67)
The merits of the utilitarian rejection of common sense morality need not be assessed, however, because utilitarianism seems

impossible to put into practice. Utilitarian support for any particular conclusion is

undermined by the inability of anyone actually to perform the kinds of calculations that

utilitarians profess to use. Whether the good is identified with happiness or preferencesatisfaction,

the two leading contenders at the moment, utilitarians announce the conclusions of



their calculations without ever being able to show the calculation itself.

When I was in school, math teachers suspected that students who could never show their work were copying answers from other

students. I suspect similarly that utilitarians, whose “calculations” often support conclusions that others reach by recourse to principles

of gratitude, retributive justice, commensuration between burdens and benefits, and so forth, reach conclusions on grounds of intuitions

influenced predominantly by these very principles.

Utilitarians may claim that, contrary to superficial appearances, these principles are themselves

supported by utilitarian calculations. But, again, no one has produced a relevant calculation.

Some principles seem prima facie opposed to utilitarianism, such as the one prescribing special solicitude of parents for their own children. It

would seem that in cold climates more good would be produced if people bought winter coats for needy children, instead of special dress coats

and ski attire for their own children. But utilitarians defend the principle of special parental concern. They declare this principle consistent with

utilitarianism by appeal to entirely untested, unsubstantiated assumptions about counterfactuals. It is a kind of “Just So” story that explains how

good is maximized by adherence to current standards. There is no calculation at all.



Another indication that utilitarians cannot perform the calculations they profess to rely upon

concerns principles whose worth is in genuine dispute. Utilitarians offer no calculations that

help to settle the matter. For example, many people wonder today whether or not patriotism is a worthy moral principle. Detailed

utilitarian calculations play no part in the discussion.

These are some of the reasons why utilitarianism provides no help to those deciding whether or not

disproportionate exposure of poor people to toxic wastes is just.

Free Market Approach

Toxic wastes, a burden, could be placed where residents accept them in return for monetary payment, a benefit. Since market transactions often

satisfactorily commensurate burdens and benefits, this approach may seem to honor the principle of commensuration between burdens and

benefits.

Unlike many market transactions, however, whole communities, acting as corporate bodies, would have to contract with those seeking to bury

wastes. Otherwise, any single individual in the community could veto the transaction, resulting in the impasse attending libertarian approaches.7

Communities could receive money to improve such public facilities as schools, parks, and hospitals, in addition to obtaining tax revenues and

jobs that result ordinarily from business expansion.

The major problem with this free market approach is that it fails to accord equal

consideration to everyone’s interests. Where basic or vital goods and services are at issue, we

usually think equal consideration of interests requires ameliorating inequalities of

distribution that markets tend to produce. For example, one reason, although not the only

reason, for public education is to provide every child with the basic intellectual tools

necessary for success in our society. A purely free market approach, by contrast, would result

in excellent education for children of wealthy parents and little or no education for children

of the nation’s poorest residents. Opportunities for children of poor parents would be so

inferior that we would say the children’s interests had not been given equal consideration.




Download 0.65 Mb.

Share with your friends:
1   ...   5   6   7   8   9   10   11   12   13




The database is protected by copyright ©ininet.org 2024
send message

    Main page