Planet Debate 2011 September/October l-d release Animal Rights


Animal Rights Strategy Fails – Ethical Arguments Insufficient to Change Attitudes



Download 1.43 Mb.
Page117/133
Date16.08.2017
Size1.43 Mb.
#33284
1   ...   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120   ...   133

Animal Rights Strategy Fails – Ethical Arguments Insufficient to Change Attitudes


ETHICAL ARGUMENTS CAN’T CHANGE OUR INTUITION TO PUT HUMANS FIRST

Richard Posner, Federal Circuit Judge, 2004, Animal Rights: Current debates and new directions, eds. Sunstein & Nussbaum, p. 67



I do not claim that our preferring human beings to other animals is “justified” in some rational sense—only that it is a fact deeply rooted in our current thinking and feeling, a fact based on beliefs that can change but not a fact that can be shaken by philosophy. I particularly do not claim that we are rationally justified in giving preference to the suffering of humans just because it is humans who are suffering. It is because we are humans that we put humans first. If we were cats, we would put cats first, regardless of what philosophers might tell us. Reason doesn’t enter.
MORAL ARGUMENT INEFFECTIVE IN CHANGING BEHAVIOR

Richard Posner, Federal Circuit Judge, 2004, Animal Rights: Current debates and new directions, eds. Sunstein & Nussbaum, p. 69

And although the efficacy and soundness of moral arguments are analytically distinct issue, they are related. One reason that moral arguments are ineffective in changing behavior is their lack of cogency—their radical inconclusiveness—in amorally diverse society such as ours, where people can and do argue from incompatible premises. But there is something deeper. Moral argument often appears plausible when it is not well reasoned or logically complete, but it is almost always implausible when it is carried to a logical extreme. An illogical utilitarian (a “soft” utilitarian, we might call him) is content to say that pain is bad, that animals experience pain, so that, other thing being equal, we should try to alleviate animal suffering if we can do so at a modest cost. Singer, a powerfully logical utilitarian, a “hard” utilitarian, is not content with such pabulum. He wants to pursue to its logical extreme the proposition that pain is bad for whoever or whatever experiences it. He does not flinch from the logical implications of his philosophy that if a stuck pig experiences more pain than a stuck human, the pig has the superior claim to our solicitude, or that a chimpanzee is entitled to more consideration than a profoundly retarded human being. (He does not flinch from these implications, but, as I said, in his popular writing, and in particular in Animal Liberation, he soft-pedals them so as not to lose his audience.)

Animal Rights Strategy Fails – Rights Can’t Pierce Anthropocentrism


ANTHROPOCENTRISM PRECLUDES PEOPLE FROM ACKNOWLEDGING OPPRESSION OF NONHUMAN ANIMALS

David Nibert, Professor of sociology, Wittenburg University, 2002, Animal Rights/Human Rights: entanglement of oppression and liberation, p. 197-8



Ethnocentrism/anthropocentrism is essential to this process. If the masses are taught to discount the oppressed as “foreign,” “alien,” ‘uncivilized,” ‘unclean,” “stupid,” “inferior,” and so on, they become socially distanced from the devalued others, thus precluding both opportunities and tendencies for empathetic response. Many humans are deeply situated in the status quo, through indoctrination, social position, and self-interest, even express indignation at any suggestion that “others” particularly other animals, are oppressed.
THOSE WHO BENEFIT FROM THE OPPRESSION OF OTHERS VIEW HIERARCHIES IN STATUS AS “NATURAL”

David Nibert, Professor of sociology, Wittenburg University, 2002, Animal Rights/Human Rights: entanglement of oppression and liberation, p. 199-200

Meanwhile, those who do not suffer oppression, and may even reap some benefits from the oppression of others, similarly are steeped in a social reality that presents the arrangement as natural. Again, drawing an example from the pervasiveness of racism in the Southern United States, civil rights activist Virginia Durr recalled:

“If you are born into a system that’s wrong, whether it’s a slave system or whether it is a segregated system, you take it for granted. And I was born into a system that was segregated and denied Blacks the right to vote, and also denied women the right to vote, and I took it for granted. Nobody told me any different, nobody said it was strange or unusual.”

Powerful ideological and social forces frequently produce distorted outlooks and dispositions that naturalize oppression, a process social theorist and educator Paolo Freire referred to as “domestication” of the human animal.

Animal Rights Strategy Fails – Ineffective Strategy for Social Change


RELIANCE ON “RIGHTS” STRATEGY FOR ANIMALS IS A HOLLOW HOPE – INEFFECTIVE AT PROMOTING SOCIAL CHANGE

Helena Silverstein, Professor, Lafayette College of Government and law, 1996, Unleashing Rights: law, meaning and the animal rights movement, p. 54



This leads us to address further concerns raised in the scholarship on rights language. Are activists captivated by the “hollow hope” of rights led to deploy an ineffective and even harmful language (Rosenberg, 1991)? And do the language and meaning of rights shape this movement in detrimental and undermining ways? These questions relate to the larger issue of whether the appropriation of rights language contributes to social movement attempts to advance social change. If recent legal scholarship is correct, there is good reason to be skeptical of the turn to rights language common in modern movements. There is reason to believe that political activists seeking to advance progressive social change are misguided by the empty promise of rights. Whether animal rights activists are misled in this way and, as a result, diminish the effectiveness of their movement and the power of rights are issues that must be addressed.

Animal Rights Strategy Fails – Focus on Rights Undermines Success of Movements


ANIMAL RIGHTS MOVEMENT FOCUSING ON PEOPLE, NOT GOVERNMENT—BUT STRATEGY IS FAILING

Robert Garner, Professor of Politics, University of Leicester, 1996, Animal Rights: the changing debate, ed. Robert Garner, p. 123-4



Whilst the cultural changes referred to in the previous paragraphs are hugely important, the animal protection movement also needs (and, more to the point, has sought) to enter into conventional pressure group politics. Clearly, it is a bankrupt strategy simply to wait for major cultural changes to somehow miraculously emerge. For one thing, the effect that governmental action can have on social behavior should not be underestimated. For another, there is much, of course, that can be done to improve the lot of animals short of the major social transformation that is no doubt needed for the achievement of the abolitionist objectives of animal rightists. Furthermore, there is some evidence that the opponents of the animal rights movement (the pharmaceutical companies, the bio-medical community and the meat industry) have mounted a relatively successful counter-mobilization so that the animal protection movement finds it much more difficult now to gain positive publicity for its campaigns.
ANIMAL RIGHTS ADVOCATES VIEWED AS ANTI-HUMAN

Helena Silverstein, Professor, Lafayette College of Government and law, 1996, Unleashing Rights: law, meaning and the animal rights movement, p. 234

As if this were not bad enough, additional problems associated with public perceptions stem from the competing claims rights often foster. Because the notion of animal rights implies a human obligation to cease most if not all current use of animals, the movement’s identity is associated with a challenge to such human rights as choosing the clothes we wear, the food we eat, and the sports in which we engage. Most importantly, the identity of this movement is connected to the assertion that it is immoral to experiment on animals. This, in turn, identifies the movement with a challenge to the human right to life.

The move from welfare to rights thus transforms the publicly perceived identity of animal activists from the traditional, somewhat derogatory image of animal lovers to the new, extremely disparaging image of human haters. Animal rights activists have come to be viewed as people who prefer animals to humans, who fight for animals when humans are still in need of protection, and who would sacrifice human lives for the lives of animals. This image is captured nicely by animal rights opponents who ask the question: Your child or your dog?

To a large extent, such public perceptions of movement identity would have occurred had animal liberation rather than animal rights come to symbolize this movement. Animal liberation, like animal rights, seeks to end the way we presently use and conceive of animals. However, the language of animal rights is especially problematic for public perceptions. It pushes the public toward the belief that the movement’s identity is about giving cows the right to vote. In so doing, the rights-oriented identity amplifies the absurdity of animal rights and reinforces common perceptions of rights.


ANIMAL RIGHTS POSITION DOESN’T ALLOW COMPROMISES -- UTOPIAN

Gary L. Francione, Professor of Law, Rutgers University, 1996, Rain Without Thunder, p. 160-1



Any response to the claim that animal rights theory is “utopian,” “unrealistic,” or “absolutist” also requires an examination of the macro components of these various theories in order to determine what each prescribes to achieve the ideal state of affairs for animals, beyond personal changes in lifestyle. It is a central tenet of new welfarism that rights theory represents an “all or nothing” approach that cannot provide a theory of incremental change. If, the argument goes, rights theory regards complete abolition as a societal ideal, and as a matter of micro-level personal behavior, then the rights advocate cannot affirmatively seek any change short of complete abolition without acting in conflict with rights theory. Since there is no realistic possibility of complete abolition anytime soon, rights theory is dismissed as “utopian” in that it seeks an ideal state without a corresponding theory about how to get there.



Download 1.43 Mb.

Share with your friends:
1   ...   113   114   115   116   117   118   119   120   ...   133




The database is protected by copyright ©ininet.org 2024
send message

    Main page