Theology beacon dictionary of theology


For Further Reading: Wiley



Download 6.66 Mb.
Page11/111
Date18.10.2016
Size6.66 Mb.
#2418
1   ...   7   8   9   10   11   12   13   14   ...   111

For Further Reading: Wiley, CT, 1:320-93; Berkhof,
Systematic Theology, 52-81; Brunner, The Christian Doc-
trine of God;
Henry, ed., Christian Faith and Modem The-
ology,
67-93; Erickson, ed., The Living God: Readings in
Christian Theology;
Barth, Church Dogmatics: The Doc-
trine of God.
Donald S. Metz

AUGSBURG CONFESSION. A declaration of Lu­theran belief, composed in 1530 by Philip Melanchthon with the approval of Luther. Me-lanchthon's own revision, in 1540, attempted to encourage ecumenical discussion by softening



58

AUGUSTINIANISM


some anti-Calvinistic and anti-Roman state­ments. The 1530 edition has been taken histori­cally as the more adequate and is called the invariata. The normative interpretation of the Confession is the Apology, also written by Me-lanchthon in 1530.

Originally, the Confession, signed by seven of the electors (political rulers) of Germany and also for the cities of Nuremberg and Reutlingen, was presented in the Diet (parliament) held by the Holy Roman Emperor Charles V, in Augsburg in 1530. The electors hoped to present Lutheranism favorably before the emperor, a sincere Catholic, and so aid in settling Reformation-born religious and political issues. The Catholic-dominated Diet declared the Confession refuted by its own Confutation. Also refuted were confessions by South German Lutherans (Tripolitana) and Ul-rich Zwingli (Ratio fidei). Neither of these was al­lowed to come directly to the Diet, however.

Attempts at compromise at Augsburg failed. The Protestants (who called themselves Evangel­icals) were ordered to recant within a year or face armed suppression. The Protestant-Roman Cath­olic division dates from this Diet. The Confession quickly became the Lutherans' principal doc­trinal authority, though its original purpose was lost.

The Confession has two major parts: 21 articles stating positive Lutheran doctrine and 7 articles outlining abuses within Roman Catholicism that Lutheranism has corrected. The spirit of the Con­fession is irenic and conservative. It cites the church fathers, canon law, and other tradi­tionally accepted authorities in addition to Scrip­ture. The Lutherans sought to demonstrate their faithfulness to historic orthodoxy (there was no hint of the later position that the abuses within Catholicism really arose from its very nature), and their positive declarations were as broadly and traditionally stated as possible.

The principal corrected abuses were: with­holding the cup from lay persons, priestly celi­bacy, believing that the Mass is a sacrifice and a meritorious work, believing that only sins specif­ically confessed to the priest can be absolved, giving traditions the force of divine command­ments, believing that the monastic life is a mer­itorious good work and the truly perfect and biblical Christian way, believing in supereroga­tory good works of monks and other saints and that they may be applied to others, and so estab­lishing episcopal authority that it is believed that a bishop may rightfully act even in contradiction to the gospel. The Epilogue hints at even more abuses corrected by Lutheranism, but these gave sufficient clue to the principles of assess­ment.

Serious theological controversies within Lu­theranism after Luther's death (1546), and con­flict with and about the Calvinists, Zwinglians, and Anabaptists threatened to sunder and de­stroy Lutheranism. In response, the contending parties formulated the Book of Concord (1580) as the basis of doctrinal agreement. It contains both the Augsburg Confession (1530) and the Apology, along with the Apostles', Nicene, and Ath-anasian creeds, the Smalcald Articles, Luther's two Catechisms, and the Formula of Concord.

See protestantism, lutheranism. For Further Reading: Schaff, Creeds of Christendom, 3:3-180; Heick, A History of Christian Thought, 1:404-17.

Paul M. Bassett

AUGUSTINIANISM. The theological and philo­sophical thought of Augustine, bishop of Hippo (354-430), has shaped the assumptions of West­ern Christianity down to the present day.

Augustine's Teachings. Augustine's thought was deeply colored by Neoplatonism, especially his doctrine of man and his theory of knowledge. Man was a body-soul dualism. The rational soul (i.e., the mind) perceived the eternal realities or "Forms" (Plato) by illumination from God and so was able to think rationally about objects in the physical, temporal world. Only by this knowl­edge of the Absolute could men make judgments about the relative.

Only the Christian with faith in the teachings of the Church and the Bible, however, truly knows God as the Holy Trinity. Augustine's doc­trine of God emphasizes the unity and equality of the three Persons, as is seen in his chosen model for the Trinity—memory, understanding, and will in the mind of man. Augustine also taught the double procession of the Spirit from the Father and the Son (filioque). This became the major theological division between the Western (Latin) church and the Greek East.

Against the Pelagians, Augustine insisted that salvation is by grace, not by merit. Evil is not an eternal principle equal to Good, as the Mani-chaeans said, but, as Neoplatonism taught, the negation of Good. Adam had free will, but his descendants, inheriting his original sin, were free only to choose evil. God's grace works irresistibly in the elect (those predestinated to salvation) till they "freely" choose the good and thus receive salvation. Those not predestinated are damned because of their own sinfulness.

The sacraments, by which this grace is infused into man, could be valid among schismatics, but





AUTHENTIC EXISTENCE—AUTHENTICITY

59


were only celebrated properly in the one Catho­lic church whose bishops stood in succession to the apostles. Not all the visible church belonged to the invisible Church (the elect).

In his philosophy of history, Augustine saw two cities engaged in struggle since the Fall—the City of God (now represented by the Church) and the earthly city, human society apart from God.



Later Augustinianism. Augustine's teachings were mediated to the Middle Ages in a coarser, more superstitious form by Gregory the Great (pope, 590-604) who did, however, moderate Augustine's doctrine of predestination. Western Christianity became quite Augustinian. In the 13th century, Alexander of Hales, Bona venture, and Duns Scotus (all Franciscans) defended the Platonist tradition of Augustinianism against the reawakened interest in Aristotle; but Thomas Aquinas, the great Dominican theologian, pro­duced a massive synthesis of Aristotelianism and Christian doctrine which became the dominant form of medieval Catholicism.

The Reformation, begun by the Franciscan Martin Luther (d. 1546), can be seen as a revival of Augustinianism in some respects. The Re­formers professed to follow much of Augustine's doctrine (notably Calvin on predestination), but not his Neoplatonist philosophy. The distinction is not so easily made, however, and much West­ern Christianity is still pervaded by Augustinian concepts and assumptions. These include the concepts of eternity as timelessness, of man as a mind-body dualism, of grace as an impersonal influence, and of the "spiritual" as esoteric and other-worldly.

See pelagianism. calvinism, wesleyanism, armin­ianism, protestantism.

For Further Reading: Heick, A History of Christian
Thought,
1:130-42, 196-206; Chadwick, The Early
Church,
216-36. T. A. NOBLE

AUTHENTIC EXISTENCE. This is a term intro­duced by the existentialist philosopher Martin Heidegger and later taken over by Jean-Paul Sar­tre. It should be paired with its correlative term, inauthentic existence, and relates to the exis­tentialist stress upon individuality and self-determination. Existence is authentic to the extent that the individual has taken possession of himself and determined his own life-style. Inau­thentic existence, on the other hand, is molded by external influences whether these be circum­stances, moral codes, or political or ecclesiastical authorities.

Heidegger felt that in the everyday routines of life, one may, and he thought usually does, be­come absorbed in the world. He tends to become part of the system, to be caught up in the pro­cesses which man himself has originated, and to become just another part of the machinery, an "organization man." This is an ironical destiny, yet it is one that has overtaken millions of people in industrial societies. This reflects one of the reasons for the existentialist reaction to the tech­nological age which stifles individuality. In inau­thentic existence the individual turns the "self" into an object among other objects and thus in Heidegger's special sense, ceases to "exist." One who lives authentically refuses to be dehu­manized by becoming subservient to a system of things; or in Sartre's version, refuses to play roles that do not truly express himself. Authentic exis­tence in relation to others involves a concern for the other which helps him to freedom and to his own unique possibilities for selfhood.

From the Christian perspective, authentic exis­tence would be better expressed by the theistic existentialist, Soren Kierkegaard. For S. K., man is created in the image of God, and thus his es­sentia/ nature entails his relation to God. His exis­tential predicament is that he is in a state of alienation from God, producing anxiety, and this would be inauthentic existence. Authenticity, in this context, would occur when man exists in right relationship to his Creator. It would not re­sult in the kind of individualistic existence out­lined by Sartre and others but rather in dependence on, radical faith in, and obedience to God.

See existential (existentialism).



For Further Reading: Blackham, Six Existentialist
Thinkers;
Heinemann, Existentialism and the Modern
Predicament.
H. RAY DUNNING

AUTHENTICITY. This term derives from the Greek authentein, to have authority or dominion over someone. The Greek term authentia came to mean the authority or author of a book. In the juridical sense, authenticity means that a book is authoritative; that is, its claims can be trusted. In this sense, authenticity is a term used in discus­sion of sacred writings, particularly the Old and New Testaments.

Apparently, Tertullian {De prascr, haer., 16) was the first to use this word with regard to the sa­cred books. Authenticity became a category for denoting books accepted as fully inspired in op­position to apocryphal writings. Books that were said to be authentic were accorded infallible au­thority. Canonical books were treated as authen­tic documents of divine revelation.





60

AUTHORITY—AWAKENING


Many would grant authenticity in the full sense only to the autographs (i.e., the original documents as written or dictated by the author). In the absence of autographs, copies are said to be authentic when they faithfully reproduce the autographs. Translations may be judged authen­tic by competent authority, which, in the case, e.g., of Roman Catholicism, is the church. The Latin Vulgate was declared authentic by the Council of Trent because the church had used it for many centuries.

Biblical criticism in the modern period has popularized the term authenticity. A book is deemed authentic if it really originated with the author and time attributed to the work. Thus, Romans is considered an authentic Pauline Epis­tle, while Hebrews is not.

In its adjectival form, authenticity has become an important philosophical and theological word. Martin Heidegger coined the expressions "authentic existence" and "inauthentic existence." Among existentialists such as Rudolf Bultmann and Paul Tillich this has gained wide usage. Christian existentialists equate "inauthentic exis­tence" with sin, and "authentic existence" is un­derstood as the life of faith in Jesus Christ. Non-Christian philosophers have a more hu­manistic understanding of "authentic existence" as self-actualization, while "inauthentic exis­tence" is the failure to realize one's potential.

See authentic existence, existential (exis­tentialism), criticism (nt), criticism (ot), textual criticism.

For Further Reading: Macquarrie, Twentieth Century
Religious Thought;
Tillich, The Courage to Be; Heidegger,
Being and Time; Kummel, Introduction to the New Testa-
ment.
Jerry W. McCant

AUTHORITY. God is the ultimate, final Authority. He is the Author with a capital A, the Creator, the First Cause, the Beginning and End of All. Every lesser authority is derived from Him, however it is used, whether for good or ill. By this voluntary delegation of lesser authorities, God has chosen in His wisdom to limit himself. In a sense there is no power but of God.

Authority is as complex and varied as life it­self. There is legal authority, derived from the will of the people, or from some official figure or constituted body. There is physical authority de­rived from brute strength, great numbers, or force of arms. There is intellectual authority de­rived from learning and/or rational superiority. There is social and economic authority derived from emotional charm and talent. There is moral authority derived from character and commit­ment. There is ecclesiastical authority derived from the Scripture and the Church. And, along with other forms of authority, there may be in certain persons or in certain groups a blending of different kinds of authentic power and influence.

Right living is to be found in the healthy bal­ance between the basic factors—one's own indi­viduality and self-determination; a positive relationship with other persons and groups; and the overarching will of God.

In writing on the sources of authority, Purkiser, Taylor, and Taylor (GMS) point out the four di­vinely appointed mediums of guidance under the sovereignty of God: the Bible, Jesus, the Holy Spirit, and the Church. They go on to say, "The three sources of authority for the Early Church merge into one for us: the New Testament." To restate this, the written Word, the Bible, inspired by the Holy Spirit, brings to us by faith the Liv­ing Word, Jesus Christ. And to move a step fur­ther, the Bible is best understood and lived out within the fellowship of Christian believers, illu­minated by the Holy Spirit.

As Roger Nicole says, the evangelical Christian seeks to avoid on the one hand "the views which pay homage to ecclesiastical tradition as coordi­nate with Scripture, and on the other hand the views which locate God's voice in some element of human nature whether conscience (moralism), emotions (romanticism), or mind (rationalism)."

Our authority is Jesus Christ, the Living Word, as revealed in the written Word and illuminated by the Holy Spirit.

See divine sovereignty, obedience, biblical au­thority.

For Further Reading: Taylor, Biblical Authority and


Christian Faith.
john E. riley

AVARICE. See covetousness. seven deadly sins.

AWAKENING. In the NT, sleep is occasionally used as a figure or image of death (Matt. 9:24; John 11:11; 1 Thess. 4:14). There is a consistent follow-through in the use of the image when a subsequent awakening comes to pass as a result of the resurrection power of Jesus Christ.

This same metaphor is also used to illustrate spiritual death. The "sleep" spoken of in Rom. 13:11; 1 Cor. 15:34; Eph. 5:14; and 1 Thess. 5:6 is of this kind. It should be noted that this sleep is not that essential rest required to maintain good health but rather a careless insensibility that should provoke alarm as in the case of the fool­ish virgins (Matt. 25:1-13). Wesley called this kind of sleep a "stupid insensibility" (NT Notes, Eph. 5:14). Spiritual laziness, self-indulgence, and irresponsibility produce this kind of lethargy.





AWE—AXIOLOGY

61


The exhortation to "awaken" is the call of God to all who are spiritually dead or asleep. It is the individual's responsibility to awaken and con­sequently Jesus Christ will "give thee light" (Eph. 5:14), righteousness (1 Cor. 15:34), and salvation (Rom. 13:11; 1 Thess. 5:9).

To be thus awakened is to experience a quick­ening (Eph. 2:1, 5) or a reviving. And this experi­ence is not limited to the individual but can also be shared corporately.

See convict (conviction), revival.

For Further Reading: Kittel, 2:333-39; Orr, The Light of the Nations; Smith, Revivalism and Social Reform.

Robert A. Mattke

AWE. See reverence.

AXIOLOGY. Axiology is the theory and study of value and disvalue; it is an investigation of the nature, types, and metaphysical status of value. The word is a compound of two Greek words, Axios (worth), and logos (reason, meaning).

In modern philosophy the word axiology has generally been replaced by the phrase value the­ory.

Axiology (or the theory of value) has (1) a wider and (2) a more narrow meaning. In its wider use, it means the general theory of all pre­scriptive predicates about what ought or ought not to be valued, and it includes the disciplines of moral theory, psychology, the social sciences, and the humanities. In its more narrow sense, "value" is limited to moral theory, in which case axiology is a part of the field of ethics.

Axiology has its roots in the pre-Socratics who asked the question of the "really real"; what is the foundation of all other values, what is it that per­sists in the midst of change? Axiology is devel­oped in Plato's theory of the Forms or Ideas which are the metaphysical archetypes of all val­ues. In the Dialogues, he discusses the meaning of the right, obligation, beauty, virtue, moral judg­ment, aesthetic value, and truth. How are all these related? Plato believed that all questions about value belong to the same family and that they finally cohere in the good, the crowning and unitive form.

For Aristotle axiology is a constant topic of in­terest. It receives treatment in the Organon, Ethics, Poetics, and the Metaphysics. For him the highest value is the ultimate final cause, God. For Thomas Aquinas also, the summum bonum (the highest good or value) is God, who is the sole Ground for all other values.

The belief that questions about the good, the right, the beautiful, etc., could be answered through metaphysics was not seriously ques­tioned until Kant's Critique of Pure Reason. Ac­cording to Kant, the inherent epistemological limitations associated with the categories, and the two forms of knowing (space and time) make such knowledge unobtainable through specu­lative reason. The second and third Critiques, as well as the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Mor­als which led to the second Critique, sought to establish another basis for value.

Hegel restored the metaphysical basis of axiol­ogy (value as the expression and self-realization of Absolute Spirit). But this restoration collapsed under the criticism of such people as Bauer, Feu-erbach, and Marx.

In the 19th century Plato's idea that questions of value belong to one family was reborn. Ac­cording to this position, questions about the good, the right, obligation, virtue, aesthetic and moral judgment, the beautiful, and truth are bet­ter dealt with when systematically thought of as components of a general theory of value and val­uation that includes economics, ethics, aesthet­ics, jurisprudence, education, and perhaps even logic and epistemology. The idea of a general theory of value was very popular early in this century on the Continent, in Latin America, and in the U.S. (e.g., Ralph Barton Perry, John Dewey, and Paul Taylor).

Value theory holds a very important place in the process metaphysics of Alfred North White­head and Charles Hartshorne. For both, God is the Comprehensive Valuer who offers to the world ideal aims, the fulfillment of which satis­fies value.

Ralph Barton Perry and Paul Taylor, who un­derstand axiology in its wider sense, distinguish eight "realms of value": morality, the arts, sci­ence, religion, economics, politics, law, and cus­tom (or etiquette).

Several meanings or forms of "value" or "the valuable" can be distinguished: (1) extrinsic or in­strumental value, i.e., valued as a means to some­thing else that is believed to be desirable or good; (2) intrinsic or inherent value or goodness, i.e., that which is judged good or valuable as an end in itself; (3) contributory value, i.e., value that contributes to a whole value of which it is a part (a violin contributes to an orchestra); (4) moral value, i.e., the sort of value or goodness that be­longs to a virtuous person, or to a morally ap­proved trait of character. (Some philosophers make an even sharper distinction between util­itarian and extrinsic or instrumental value, and



62

BAALISM


between inherent or intrinsic value. But these distinctions seem to be forced.)

A distinction is also made between normative and nonnormative values. For those who believe that this is a proper distinction, some values are held to be normative, i.e., binding on everyone. Values that are judged normative are indepen­dent of the valuer's preferences. They ought to be valued; hence they are judged to be religiously or morally compelling. By contrast nonnormative values do arise from preference, e.g., when a per­son prefers one form of art over another. In this case it is, or should be, understood that the value is not generally binding; it carries no religious or moral authority.

Partly through the influence of language anal­ysis philosophers, there is significant disagree­ment over whether values are cognitive or noncognitive in nature. Those who hold the first view believe that some values are normative, that they ought to be adhered to because they express ontological realities whose authority is indepen­dent of human preference, i.e., they have a purely objective basis. Such values denote a real property that transcends the desires and esti­mates of the valuing subject. Some phenom-enologists, for instance, say that our experience of "normative values" is actually an experience of objective ethical essences that are recognized or discovered and that do not depend simply on one's choice of them.

Noncognitivists such as A. J. Ayer and Bertrand Russell deny the objectivity of values. They insist that all values are expressions of societal or indi­vidual preference. They express no absolutes, but are wholly expressions of attitudes, desires, and emotions. Accordingly, values are not pre­scriptive, i.e., they cannot tell us what people ought to value, but descriptive, i.e., they simply indicate what people in various times and under various circumstances choose to value. The philo­sopher's task is not to tell people what to value, but to examine the meaning of value language. What are we doing when we say that something is valuable? How do communities employ this language?

For some only one thing is valuable. For Aris­totle this is Eudaemonia (excellent activity); for Augustine and Aquinas it is communion with God; for F. H. Bradley it is self-realization; for Neitzsche it is power. Other philosophers are more pluralistic; they hold that a number of things are good or good-making in themselves. These thinkers include Plato, G. E. Moore, W. D. Ross, Max Scheler, Nicolai Hartmann, and Ralph Barton Perry. Their list of "the valuable" include two or more of the following: pleasure, knowl­edge, aesthetic experience, beauty, truth, virtue, harmony, love, friendship, justice, freedom, and self-expression.

For some recent Protestant theologians, such as Bonhoeffer, Brunner, and Barth, the good is what God wills, vis., His word of creation, re­demption, and fulfillment, spoken preeminently through the incarnation of God in Christ and His sanctification of human life in the world.

See values, values clarification, absolutes,

duty, beauty.


Directory: sites -> default -> files -> publications
publications -> Table of Content forward introduction
publications -> Rehabilitation Engineering Research Center for Wireless Technologies Georgia Institute of Technology
publications -> Housing Counseling Research in Chicago
publications -> Communicating with Aboriginal and Torres Strait Islander Audiences
publications -> New Brunswick Info Sheet on First Nations Child Welfare
publications -> Paap’s Electronic Newsletter 14 November 2008 Volume 11 Number 22 towards ‘smart’ subsidies in agriculture: lessons from recent experience in malawi
publications -> Information support of pedagogical process for the children experiencing difficulties with acquisition of preschool educational programs
publications -> Asus’ ZenFone ar has Google’s augmentted and virtual reality baked in — but not combined
publications -> School Readiness and Early Grade Success Consultation Memo Atlanta, ga

Download 6.66 Mb.

Share with your friends:
1   ...   7   8   9   10   11   12   13   14   ...   111




The database is protected by copyright ©ininet.org 2024
send message

    Main page